Friday, December 20, 2019

Investing in the Unknown and Unknowable



                                                                            Capitalism and Society

Volume 1, Issue 2                           2006                                         Article 5

Investing in the Unknown and Unknowable

Richard Zeckhauser Harvard University 
Copyright (c) 2006 The Berkeley Electronic Press.  All rights reserved

                            Abstract

  
From David Ricardo making a fortune buying British government bonds on the eve of the Battle of Waterloo to Warren Buffett selling insurance to the California earthquake authority, the wisest investors have earned extraordinary returns by investing in the unknown and hte unknowable (UU).  But they have done so on a reasoned, sensible basis.  This easay explains some of the central principles that such investors employ.  It starts by discussing "ignorance," a widespread situation in the real world of investing, where even the possible states of the world are not known.  Traditional finance theory does not apply in UU situations.
Strategic thinking, deducing what other investors might know or not, and assessing whether they might be deterred from investing, for example due to fiduciary requirements, frequently point the way to profitability.  Most big investment payouts come when money is combined with complementary skills, such as knowing how to develop real estate or new technologies.  Those who lack these skills can look for "sidecar" investments that allow them to put their money alongside that of people they know to be both capable and honest. The reader is asked to consider a number of usch investments.
Central concepts in decision analysis, game theory, and behavioral decision are deployed along-side real investment decisions to unearch successful investment strategies.  There strategies are distiled into eight investment maxims.  Learning to invest more wisely in a UU world may be the most promising way to significantly bolster your properity.
KEYWORDS: investing, unknown, unknowable, sidecar investment, fattailed distribution, buffett, Kelly Criterion, asymmetric information.
David Ricardo made a fortune buying bonds from the British government four days in advance of the Battle of Waterloo. He was not a military analyst, and even if he were, he had no basis to compute the odds of Napoleon’s defeat or victory, or hard-to-identify ambiguous outcomes. Thus, he was investing in the unknown and the unknowable. Still, he knew that competition was thin, that the seller was eager, and that his windfall pounds should Napoleon lose would be worth much more than the pounds he’d lose should Napoleon win. Ricardo knew a good bet when he saw it.1

This essay discusses how to identify good investments when the level of uncertainty is well beyond that considered in traditional models of finance. Many of the investments considered here are one-time only, implying that past data will be a poor guide. In addition, the essay will highlight investments, such as real estate development, that require complementary skills. Most readers will not have such skills, but many will know others who do. When possible, it is often wise to make investments alongside them.

Though investments are the ultimate interest, the focus of the analysis is how to deal with the unknown and unknowable, hereafter abbreviated UU.  Hence, I will sometimes discuss salient problems outside of finance, such as terrorist attacks, which are also unknown and unknowable.

This essay takes no derivatives, and runs no regressions.2 In short, it eschews the normal tools of my profession. It represents a blend of insights derived from reading academic works and from trying to teach their insights to others, and from lessons learned from direct and at-a-distance experiences with a number of successful investors in the UU world. To reassure my academic audience, I use footnotes where possible, though many refer to accessible internet articles in preference to journals and books. Throughout this essay, you will find speculations and maxims, as seems called for by the topic. They will be labeled in sequence.

This informal approach seems appropriate given our present understanding of the topic. Initial beliefs about this topic are highly uncertain, or as statisticians would phrase it: “Prior distributions are diffuse.” Given that, the judicious use of illustrations, and prudent attempts to provide taxonomies and sort tea leaves, can substantially hone our beliefs, that is, tighten our future predictions.

Part I of this essay talks about risk, uncertainty, and ignorance, the last carrying us beyond traditional discussions. Part II looks at behavioral economics, the tendency for humans to deviate in systematic ways from rational decision, particularly when probabilities are involved, as they always are with investments. Behavioral economics pervades the UU world. Part III addresses the role of skilled mathematical types now so prevalent in finance. It imparts a general lesson: If super-talented people will be your competitors in an investment arena, perhaps it is best not to invest. Its second half discusses a dispute between math types on money management, namely how much of your money to invest when you do have an edge.  Part IV details when to invest when you can make more out of an investment, but there is a better informed person on the other side of the transaction. Part V tells a Buffett tale, and draws appropriate inferences. Part VI concludes.


I.  RISK, UNCERTAINTY AND IGNORANCE

Escalating challenges to effective investing. The essence of effective investment is to select assets that will fare well when future states of the world become known. When the probabilities of future states of assets are known, as the efficient markets hypothesis posits, wise investing involves solving a sophisticated optimization problem. Of course, such probabilities are often unknown, banishing us from the world of the capital asset pricing model (CAPM), and thrusting us into the world of uncertainty.3

Were the financial world predominantly one of mere uncertainty, the greatest financial successes would come to those individuals best able to assess probabilities. That skill, often claimed as the domain of Bayesian decision theory, would swamp sophisticated optimization as the promoter of substantial returns.

The real world of investing often ratchets the level of non-knowledge into still another dimension, where even the identity and nature of possible future states are not known. This is the world of ignorance. In it, there is no way that one can sensibly assign probabilities to the unknown states of the world. Just as traditional finance theory hits the wall when it encounters uncertainty, modern decision theory hits the wall when addressing the world of ignorance. I shall employ the acronym UU to refer to situations where both the identity of possible future states of the world as well as their probabilities are unknown and unknowable. Table 1 outlines the three escalating categories; entries are explained throughout the paper.



This essay has both dreary and positive conclusions about investing in a UU world. The first dreary conclusion is that unknowable situations are widespread and inevitable. Consider the consequences for financial markets of global warming, future terrorist activities, or the most promising future technologies. These outcomes are as unknowable today as were the 1997 Asian meltdown, the 9/11 attacks, or the NASDAQ soar and swoon at the end of the century, shortly before they were experienced.

These were all aggregate unknowables, affecting a broad swath of investors. But many unknowables are idiosyncratic or personal, affecting only individuals or

miles to the west of the city, will they come? Will the Vietnamese government let me sell my insurance product on a widespread basis? Will my friend’s new software program capture the public fancy, or if not might it succeed in a completely different application? Such idiosyncratic UU situations, I argue below, present the greatest potential for significant excess investment returns.

The second dreary conclusion is that most investors – whose training, if any, fits a world where states and probabilities are assumed known – have little idea of how to deal with the unknowable. When they recognize its presence, they tend to steer clear, often to protect themselves from sniping by others. But for all but the simplest investments, entanglement is inevitable – and when investors do get entangled they tend to make significant errors.

The first positive conclusion is that unknowable situations have been and will be associated with remarkably powerful investment returns. The second positive conclusion is that there are systematic ways to think about unknowable situations. If these ways are followed, they can provide a path to extraordinary expected investment returns. To be sure, some substantial losses are inevitable, and some will be blameworthy after the fact. But the net expected results, even after allowing for risk aversion, will be strongly positive.
Do not read on, however, if blame aversion is a prime concern: The world of UU is not for you. Consider this analogy. If in an unknowable world none of your bridges fall down, you are building them too strong. Similarly, if in an unknowable world none of your investment looks foolish after the fact, you are staying too far away from the unknowable.

Warren Buffett, a master at investing in the unknowable, and therefore a featured player in this essay, is fond of saying that playing contract bridge is the best training for business. Bridge requires a continual effort to assess probabilities in at best marginally knowable situations, and players need to make hundreds of decisions in a single session, often balancing expected gains and losses. But players must also continually make peace with good decisions that lead to bad outcomes, both one’s own decisions and those of a partner. Just this peacemaking skill is required if one is to invest wisely in an unknowable world.

The nature of unknowable events. Many of the events that we classify as unknowable arrive in an unanticipated thunderclap, giving us little or no time to anticipate or prepare. But once they happen, they do not appear that strange. The human mind has an incredible ability to find a rationalization for why it should have been able to conjecture the terror attack of 9/11; or the Asian tsunamis of 1997 and 2005, respectively caused by currency collapse and underwater earthquake. This propensity to incorporate hindsight into our memories – and to do so particularly our ability to anticipate extreme events in the future. We learn insufficiently from our misestimates and mistaken decisions.

Other unknowable events occur over a period of time, as did the collapse of the Soviet Union. Consider most stock market swings. Starting in January 1996, the NASDAQ rose five-fold in four years. Then it reversed field and fell by two thirds in three years. Such developments are hardly thunderclaps. They are more like blowing up a balloon and then dribbling out the air. In retrospect, these remarkable swings have lost the flavor of an unknowable event, even though financial markets are not supposed to work that way. If securities prices at any moment incorporate all relevant information, a property that is usually posited, long-term movements in one direction are hardly possible, since strong runs of unanticipated good news or bad news will be exceedingly rare. Similarly, the AIDS scourge now seems familiar territory, though 25 years ago – when there had been only 31 cumulative deaths in the U.S. from AIDS – no one would have predicted a world-wide epidemic killing tens of millions and vastly disrupting the economies of many poor nations.

Are UU events to be feared? Warren Buffett (1996) once remarked: “It is essential to remember that virtually all surprises are unpleasant.”  Most salient  UU events seem to fall into the left tail of unfortunate occurrences. This may be more a matter of perception than reality. Often an upside unknowable event, say the diminution of terror attacks or recovery from a dread disease, is difficult to recognize. An attack on any single day was not likely anyway, and the patient still feels lousy on the road to recovery. Thus, the news just dribbles in, as in a financial market upswing. B.F. Skinner, the great behavioral psychologist, taught us that behavior conditioned by variable interval reinforcement – engage in the behavior and from time-to-time the system will be primed to give you a payoff – was the most difficult to extinguish. Subjects could never be sure that another reward would not be forthcoming. Similarly, it is hard to discern when a string of inconsistently spaced episodic events has concluded. If the events are unpleasant, it is not clear when to celebrate their end.

Let us focus for the moment on thunderclap events. They would not get this title unless they involved something out of the ordinary, either good or bad. Casual empiricism – judged by looking at local, national and international headlines – suggests that thunderclap events are disproportionately adverse. Unlike in the old television show, The Millionaire, people do not knock on your door to give you a boatload of money, and in Iraq terror attacks outnumber terrorist arrests manifold.

The financial arena may be one place with an apparently good ratio of upside to downside UU events, particularly if we include events that are drifts and not thunderclaps. By the end of 2004, there were 2.5 million millionaires in the United States, excluding housingwealth.

http://money.cnn.com/2005/06/09/news/world_wealth/ Many of these individuals, no doubt, experienced upside UU events. Some events, such as the sustained boom in housing prices, were experienced by many, but many upside events probably only affected the individual and perhaps a few others; such events include an unexpected lucrative job, or having a business concept take a surprisingly prosperous turn, or having a low-value real estate holding explode in value, etc.

We hear about the lottery winner -- the big pot, the thunderclap, and the gain for one individual makes it newsworthy. In contrast, the tens of thousands of UU events that created thousands of new real estate millionaires are mostly reported in dry aggregate statistics. Moreover, contrary to the ads in the back of magazines, there is usually not a good way to follow these “lucky folks,” since some complementary skill or knowledge is likely to be required, not merely money and a wise choice of an investment. Thus, many favorable UU financial events are likely to go unchronicled.

While still in this Pollyannish frame, it is worth noting the miracles of percentage symmetry given extreme events. Posit that financial prices move in some symmetric fashion. Given that negative prices are not possible, such changes must be in percentage rather than absolute terms.4  We will not notice  any difference between percentage and absolute if changes are small relative to the mean. Thus, if a price of 100 goes up or down by an average of 3 each year, or up by a ratio of 103/100 or down by 100/103 hardly matters. But change that 3 to a 50, and the percentage symmetry helps a great deal. The price becomes 100(150/100) or 100(100/150)), which has an average of 117. If prices are anything close to percentage symmetric, as many believe they are, then big swings are both enemy and friend: enemy because they impose big risks, friend because they offer substantial positive expected value.

Many millionaires have made investments that multiplied their money 10- fold, and some 100-fold. The symmetric geometric model would expect events that cut one’s stake to 1/10th or 1/100th of its initial value to be equally likely. The opportunity to get a 10 or 100 multiple on your investment as often as you lose virtually all of it is tremendously attractive.

There is, of course, no reason why investments must yield symmetric geometric returns. But it would be surprising not to see significant expected excess returns to investments that have three characteristics addressed in this essay: (1) UU underlying features, (2) complementary capabilities are required to

undertake them, so the investments are not available to the general market, and
(3) it is unlikely that a party on the other side of the transaction is better informed. That is, UU may well work for you, if you can identify general characteristics of when such investments are desirable, and when not.

These very attractive three-pronged investments will not come along everyday. And when they do, they are unlikely to scale up as much as the  investor would like, unlike an investment in an underpriced NYSE stock, which scales nicely, at least over the range for most individual investors. Thus, the UU- sensitive investor should be constantly on the lookout for new opportunities. That is why Warren Buffett trolls for new businesses to buy in each Berkshire- Hathaway annual report, and why most wealthy private investors are constantly looking for new instruments or new deals.

Uniqueness. Many UU situations deserve a third U, for unique. If they do, arbitrageurs – who like to have considerable past experience to guide them – will steer clear. So too will anybody who would be severely penalized for a poor decision after the fact. An absence of competition from sophisticated and well- monied others spells the opportunity to buy underpriced securities.

Most great investors, from David Ricardo to Warren Buffett, have made most of their fortunes by betting on UUU situations. Ricardo allegedly made 1 million pounds (over $50 million today) – roughly half of his fortune at death – on his Waterloo bonds.5 Buffett has made dozens of equivalent investments. Though he is best known for the Nebraska Furniture Mart and See’s Candies, or for long-term investments in companies like the Washington Post and Coca Cola, insurance has been Berkshire Hathaway’s firehose of wealth over the years. And insurance often requires UUU thinking. A whole section below discusses Buffett’s success with what many experts saw as a UUU insurance situation, so they steered clear; but he saw it as offering excess premium relative to risk, so he took it all.

Speculation 1: UUU investments – unknown, unknowable and unique – drive off speculators, which creates the potential for an attractive low price.

Some UU situations that appear to be unique are not, and thus fall into categories that lend themselves to traditional speculation.  Corporate takeover  bids are such situations. When one company makes a bid for another, it is often impossible to determine what is going on or what will happen, suggesting uniqueness. But since dozens of such situations have been seen over the years, speculators are willing to take positions in them. From the standpoint of investment, uniqueness is lost, just as the uniqueness of each child matters not to those who manufacture sneakers.

Weird Causes and Fat Tails. The returns to UUU investments can be extreme. We are all familiar with the Bell Curve (or Normal Distribution), which nicely describes the number of flips of a fair coin that will come up heads in a large number of trials. But such a mechanical and controlled problem is extremely rare. Heights are frequently described as falling on a Bell Curve. But in fact there are many too many people who are extremely tall or extremely short, due say to glandular disturbances or genetic abnormalities. The standard model often does not apply to observations in the tails. So too with most disturbances to investments. Whatever the explanation for the October 1987 crash, it was not due to the usual factors that are used to explain market movements.6

More generally, movements in financial markets and of investments in general appear to have much thicker tails than would be predicted by Brownian motion, the instantaneous source of Bell Curve outcomes. That may be because the fundamental underlying factors produce thicker tails, or because there are rarely occurring anomalous or weird causes that produce extreme results, or both. The UU and UUU models would give great credence to the latter explanation, though both could apply.7

Complementary skills and UU investments. A great percentage of UU investments, and a greater percentage of those that are UUU, provide great returns to a complementary skill. For example, many of America’s great fortunes in recent years have come from real estate. These returns came to people who knew where to build, and what and how. Real estate developers earn vast amounts on their capital because they have complementary skills. Venture capitalists can secure extraordinary returns on their own monies, and charge impressive fees to their investors, because early stage companies need their skills and their connections. In short, the return to these investments comes from the combination of scarce skills and wise selection of companies for investment. High tech pioneers – Bill Gates is an extreme example – get even better multiples on their investment dollars as a complement to their vision and scientific insight.8

Alas, few of us possess the skills to be a real estate developer, venture capitalist or high tech pioneer. But how about becoming a star of ordinary stock investment? For such efforts an ideal complementary skill is unusual judgment. Those who can sensibly determine when to plunge into and when to refrain from UUU investments gain a substantial edge, since mispricing is likely to be severe. Bill Miller, the famed manager of the Legg Mason Value Fund, had a unique record of beating the S&P; his string through December 2005 was 15 years in a row. In October 2004 he spoke at Harvard University, and explained in detail why he made major purchases of Google at its public offering, surely a UUU situation given the nature of the company and the fact that it was offered through a Dutch auction.9 Virtually all in the audience were impressed that he made this decision -- the stock came out at $85 in August that year and had run up to $140. But Miller recognized that explaining past successes is not a challenge. He went on to proclaim Google a great investment for the future. How right he was. Google was selling at $380 in September 2006, when this essay was completed. Alas, 2006 was not kind to Miller. By September, his Value Fund was 12% behind the S&P for the year. Only time will tell whether Miller has lost his touch or is merely in a slump.

Warren Buffett’s unusual judgment operates with more prosaic  companies, such as oil producers and soft drink firms. He is simply a genius at everyday tasks, such as judging management capability or forecasting company progress. He drains much of the unknowable in judging a company’s future. But he has other advantages. A number of Buffett’s investments have come to him because companies sought him out, asking him to make an investment and also to serve on their board, valuing his discretion, his savvy, and his reputation for rectitude – that is, his complementary skills, not merely his money. And when he is called on for such reasons, he often gets a discounted price. Those like Miller

and Buffet, who can leverage complementary skills in stock market investment, will be in a privileged position of limited competition. But that will accomplish little if they do not show courage and make big purchases where they expect high payoffs. But the lesson for regular mortals is not to imitate Warren Buffett or Bill Miller; that makes no more sense than trying to play tennis like Roger Federer. Each of them has an inimitable skill. If you lack Buffett-Miller capabilities, you will get chewed up as a bold stock picker.

Note, by the way, the generosity with which great investors with complementary skills explain their successes – Buffett in his annual reports, Miller at Harvard, and any number of venture capitalists who come to lecture to MBAs. These master investors need not worry about the competition, since few others possess the complementary skills for their types of investments. Few UU investment successes come from catching a secret, such as the whispered hint of “plastics” in the movie The Graduate. Mayer Amschel Rothschild had five sons who were bright, disciplined, loyal and willing to disperse. These were the complementary skills. The terrific investments in a UU world – and the Rothschild fortune – followed.

Before presenting a maxim about complementary skills, I present you with a decision problem. You have been asked to join the Business Advisory Board of a company named Tengion. Tengion was founded in 2003 to develop and commercialize a medical breakthrough: “developing new human tissues and organs (neo-tissues and neo-organs) that are derived from a patient’s own cells…[this technology] harnesses the body’s ability to regenerate, and it has the potential to allow adults and children with organ failure to have functioning organs built from their own (autologous) tissues.” http://www.tengion.com/

This is assuredly a UU situation, doubly so for you, since until now you had never heard the term neo-organ. A principal advantage of joining is that you would be able to invest a reasonable sum on the same basis as the firm’s insiders and venture capitalists. Would you choose to do so?

I faced this decision problem because I had worked successfully with Tengion’s president on another company many years earlier. I was delighted with the UU flavor of the situation, and chose to join and invest because I would be doing so on the same terms as sophisticated venture capital (VC) firms with track records and expertise in relevant biotech areas. This was an investment from which virtually everyone else would be excluded. In addition, it would benefit from the complementary skills of the VCs.

Sidecar investments. Such undertakings are “sidecar investments”; the investor rides along in a sidecar pulled by a powerful motorcycle. The more the investor is distinctively positioned to have confidence in the driver’s integrity and his motorcycle’s capabilities, the more attractive the investment, since its price will be lower due to limited competition. Perhaps the premier sidecar investment ever available to the ordinary investor was Berkshire Hathaway, many decades back. One could have invested alongside Warren Buffett, and had him take a ridiculously low compensation for his services. (In recent years, he has been paid
$100,000, with no bonus or options.) But in 1960 who had heard of Warren Buffett, or knew that he would be such a spectacular and poorly compensated investor? Someone who knew Buffett and recognized his remarkable capabilities back then was in a privileged UU situation.

Maxim A: Individuals with complementary skills enjoy great positive excess returns from UU investments. Make a sidecar investment alongside them when given the opportunity.

Do you have the courage to apply this maxim? It is January 2006 and you, a Western investor, are deciding whether to invest in Gazprom, the predominantly government-owned Russian natural gas giant in January 2006. Russia is attempting to attract institutional investment from the West; the stock is sold as an ADR, and is soon to be listed on the OTC exchange; the company is fiercely profitable, and it is selling gas at a small fraction of the world price. On the upside, it is generally known that large numbers of the Russian elite are investors, and here and there it is raising its price dramatically. On the downside, Gazprom is being employed as an instrument of Russian government policy, e.g., gas is sold at a highly subsidized price to Belarus, because of its sympathetic government, yet the Ukraine is being threatened with more than a four-fold increase in price, in part because its government is hostile to Moscow. And the company is bloated and terribly managed. Finally, experiences, such as those with Yukos Oil, make it clear that the government is powerful, erratic, and ruthless.

This is clearly a situation of ignorance, or UU. The future states of the world are simply not known. Will the current government stay in power? Will it make Gazprom its flagship for garnering Western investment? If so, will it streamline its operations? Is it using foreign policy concerns as a device mainly to raise prices, a strong positive, and is it on a path to raise prices across the board? Will it complete its proposed pipelines to Europe?  What questions haven’t you thought of, whose answers could dramatically affect your payout? Of course, you should also determine whether Western investors have distinct disadvantages as Gazprom shareholders, such as unique taxes, secondary voting status, etc. Finally, if you determine the investment is favorable given present circumstances, you should ask how quickly Russia could change conditions against outsiders, and whether you will be alert and get out if change begins.
You could never learn about the unknowables sufficiently well to do traditional due diligence on a Gazprom investment. The principal arguments for going ahead would be that Speculation 1 and Maxim A apply. If you could comfortably determine that the Russian elite was investing on its own volition, and that foreigners would not be discriminated against, or at least not quickly, this would make a sensible sidecar investment.10

II.  BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS AND DECISION TRAPS

Behavioral decision has shaken the fields of economics and finance in recent decades. Basically, this work shows in area after area that individuals systematically deviate from making decisions in a manner that would be admired by Jimmie Savage (1954) and Howard Raiffa (1968), pioneers of the rational decision paradigm. As one illustration, such deviators could be turned into money pumps: They would pay to pick gamble B over gamble A. Then with A reframed as A’, but not changed in its fundamentals, they would pay to pick A over B.

That is hardly the path to prudent investment, but alas behavioral decision has strong descriptive validity. Behavioral decision has important implications  for investing in UU situations. When considering our own behavior, we must be extremely careful not to fall prey to the biases and decision traps it chronicles. Almost by definition, UU situations are those where our experience is likely to be limited, where we will not encounter situations similar to other situations that have helped us hone our intuition.

Virtually all of us fall into important decision traps when dealing with the unknowable. This section discusses two, overconfidence and recollection bias, and then gives major attention to a third, misweighting differences in probabilities and payoffs. But there are dozens of decision traps, and some will appear later in this essay. The Nobel Prize winning work of Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky (the latter was warmly cited, but died too soon to win), 11 and the delightful and insightful Poor Charlie’s Almanack, written by Charles Munger (Warren Buffett’s partner) respectively provide academic and finance-oriented discussions of such traps.

There are at least three major objections to behavioral economics: First, in competitive markets, the anomalies it describes will be arbitraged away. Second, the anomalies only appear in carefully crafted situations; they are much like optical illusions, intriguing but rarely affecting everyday vision. Third, they describe the objection is tangential to this discussion; competitive markets and arbitrage are not present in many UU situations, and in particular not the ones that interest us. The second objection is relatively unimportant because, in essence, UU situations are those where optical illusions rule the world. A UU world is not unlike a Fun House. Objection three I take up seriously below; this essay is designed to help people behave more rationally when they invest.

Let us first look at the biases.

Overconfidence. When individuals are assessing quantities about which they know very little, they are much too confident of their knowledge (Alpert and Raiffa, 1982). Appendix A offers you a chance to test your capabilities in this regard.  For each of eight unknown quantities, such as the area of Finland, you are asked to provide your median estimate, then your 25th and 75th percentile estimates (i.e., it is one quarter likely the true value will be more extreme than either of the two), and then your 1st and 99th percentiles, what are referred to as surprise points. In theory, an individual should have estimates outside her surprise points about 2% of the time. In fact, even if warned about overconfidence, individuals are surprised about 35% of the time.12 Quite simply, individuals think they know much more about unknowable quantities than they do.

Speculation 2: Individuals who are overconfident of their knowledge will fall  prey to poor investments in the UU world. Indeed, they are the green plants in the elaborate ecosystem of finance where there are few lions, like Bill Miller and Warren Buffett; many gazelles, like you and me; and vast acres of grass ultimately nourishing us all.

Recollection bias. A first lesson in dealing with UU situations is to know thyself. One good way to do this is to review successes and failures in past decisions. However, since people do not have a long track record, they naturally turn to hypotheticals from the past: Would I have judged the event that actually occurred to be likely? Would I have made that good investment and steered clear of the other bad one? Would I have sold out of NASDAQ stocks near New Year 2001? Alas, human beings do not do well with such questions. They are subject to substantial recollection bias.13

Judging by articles in the New York Times leading up to 9/11/2001, there was a clear UUU event. But that is not what respondents told us one to three  years later. They were asked to compare their present assessments of the likelihood of a massive terrorist attack with what they estimated that likelihood to be on September 1, 2001. Of more than 300 Harvard Law and Kennedy School students surveyed, 31% rated the risk as now lower, and 26% rated the risk as the same as they had perceived the 9/11 risk before the event.14 We can hardly be confident that investors will be capable of judging how they would have assessed UU risks that occurred in the past.

Misweighting probabilities and preferences. The two critical components of decision problems are payoffs and probabilities. Effective decision requires that both be carefully calibrated. Not surprisingly, Prospect Theory, the most important single contribution to behavioral decision theory to date, finds that individuals’ responses to payoffs and probabilities are far from rational.15 To my knowledge, there is no tally of which contributes more to the loss of expected utility from the rational norm. (Some strong supporters of behavioral decision theory, however, think it is our norms that are misguided, and that the way the brain naturally perceives outcomes, not the prescriptions of decision theorists and economists, should be the guideline.)

Whether drawing from Prospect Theory or observation, it seems clear that individuals draw insufficient distinctions among small probabilities. Consider the following experiment, in which an individual is asked to pick A or B.

Lottery Choice: Payoffs Versus Probabilities



Payoff
Probability
A
$2000
0.01
B
$1000
0.025

A rational, risk averse individual should opt for B, since it offers a higher expected value – $25 versus $20 – and less risk. Yet past experiments have  shown that many individuals choose A, since in accordance with Prospect Theory they do not distinguish sufficiently between two low probability events. We speculate further that if we used named contingencies – for example, the Astros or the Blue Jays win the World Series – alongside their probabilities, the frequency of preference for A would increase. The contingencies would be selected, of course, so that their likelihood of occurrence, as indicated by odds in Las Vegas, would match those in the example above.

This hypothetical experiment establishes a baseline for another one that involves UU events. This time the prizes are based on events that are as close to the spectrum of UU events as possible, subject to the limitation that they must be named.16 Thus, a contingency might be that a 10,000-ton asteroid passed within 50,000 miles of Earth within the past decade, or that more than a million mammals crossed the border from Tanzania to Kenya last year. To begin our experiment, we ask a random sample of people to guess the likelihood of these contingencies. We then alter the asteroid distance or the number of animals in the question until the median answer is 0.03. Thus, if 50,000 miles got a median answer of 0.05, we would adjust to 40,000 miles, etc.

We now ask a new group of individuals to choose between C and D, assuming that we have calibrated the asteroid and mammal question to get to  0.03.

Lottery Choice: Payoffs Versus Probability or UU Event



Payoff
Required contingency
C
$2000
Draw a 17 from an urn with balls numbered 1 to 100
D
$1000
10,000-ton asteroid passed within 40,000 miles of Earth

Lotteries C and D should yield their prizes with estimated probabilities of 1% and 3% respectively. Still, we suspect that many more people would pick C over D than picked A over B, and that this would be true for the animal  movement contingency as well.17

A more elaborated version of this problem would offer prizes based on alternative UU contingencies coming to pass. For example, we might recalibrate the mammal-crossing problem to get a median response of 0.01. We would then have:

Lottery Choice: Payoffs Versus UU Events



Payoff
Required contingency
E
$2000
Calibrated large number of animals crossed the Tanzania- Kenya border
F
$1000
10,000 ton-asteroid passed within 40,000 miles of Earth

Here the values have been scaled so the median response is three times higher for the asteroid event than the animal crossing. We would conjecture again that E would be chosen frequently.18 People do not like to rely on the occurrence of UU events, and choices based on distinguishing among their probabilities would be an unnatural act.

Daniel Ellsberg (1961) alerted us to ambiguity aversion long before he created a UU event by publishing the Pentagon papers. In an actual experiment, he showed, in effect, that individuals preferred to win a prize if a standard coin flip came up heads, rather than to win that prize by choosing either heads or tails on the flip of a mangled coin whose outcome was difficult to predict.19 Such ambiguity aversion may be a plausible heuristic response to general decisions under uncertainty, since so often there is a better-informed person on the other side – such as someone selling a difficult-to-assess asset.20 Whatever the explanation, ambiguity aversion has the potential to exert a powerful effect. Extending Ellsberg one step further, it would seem that the more ambiguous the contingencies, the greater the aversion. If so, UU investments will drive away all but the most self-directed and rational thinking investors. Thus, Speculation 1 is reinforced.

III.  MATH WHIZZES IN FINANCE AND CASH MANAGEMENT

The major fortunes in finance, I would speculate, have been made by people who are effective in dealing with the unknown and unknowable. This will probably be truer still in the future. Given the influx of educated professionals into finance, those who make their living speculating and trading in traditional markets are increasingly up against others who are tremendously bright and tremendously well-informed.21
By contrast, those who undertake prudent speculations in the unknown will be amply rewarded. Such speculations may include ventures into uncharted areas, where the finance professionals have yet to run their regressions, or may take completely new paths into already well-traveled regions.22 It used to be said that if your shoeshine boy gave you stock tips it was time to get out of the market. With shoeshine boys virtually gone and finance Ph.D.’s plentiful, the new wisdom might be:

When your math whiz finance Ph.D. tells you that he and his peers have been hired to work in the XYZ field, the spectacular returns in XYZ field have probably vanished forever.

Similarly, the more difficult a field is to investigate, the greater will be the unknown and unknowables associated with it, and the greater the expected profits to those who deal sensibly with them. Unknownables can’t be transmuted into sensible guesses -- but one can take one’s positions and array one’s claims so that unknowns and unknowables are mostly allies, not nemeses. And one can train to avoid one’s own behavioral decision tendencies, and to capitalize on those of others.

Assume that an investor is willing to invest where he has an edge in UU situations. How much capital should then be placed into each opportunity? This problem is far from the usual portfolio problem. It is afflicted with ignorance, and decisions must be made in sequential fashion. Math whizzes have discussed this problem in a literature little known to economists, but frequently discussed among gamblers and mathematicians. The most famous contribution is an article published 50 years ago by J.L. Kelly, an AT&T scientist. His basic formula, which is closely related to Claude Shannon’s information theory, tells you how much to bet on each gamble as a function of your bankroll, with the probability of winning and the odds as the two parameters. Perhaps surprisingly, the array of future investment opportunities does not matter.

Kelly’s Criterion, as it is called, is to invest an amount equal to W – (1- W)/R, where W is your probability of winning, and R is the ratio of the amount you win when you win to the amount you lose when you lose. Thus, if you were 60% likely to win an even money bet, you would invest .6 – (1-.6)/1 = .2 or 20% of your capital.

It can be shown that given sufficient time, the value given by any other investment strategy will eventually be overtaken in value by following the Kelly Criterion, which maximizes the geometric growth rate of the portfolio. That  might seem to be definitive. But even in the mathematical realm of optimal dynamic investment strategies, assuming that all odds and probabilities are known, we encounter a UU situation.

Paul Samuelson, writing in a playful mood, produced an article attacking the Kelly Criterion as a guide for practice. His article uses solely one-syllable words. His abstract observes: “He who acts in N plays to make his mean log of wealth as big as it can be made will, with odds that go to one as N soars, beat me who acts to meet my own tastes for risk.”23  Samuelson correctly prescribes that  in favorable-odds situations, whether repeated or not, the optimal amount for an individual who maximizes his expected utility to invest will depend on his utility function. To promote your intuition, consider a polar case. A  risk-neutral  investor should invest his total wealth whenever he confronts a favorable-odds situation, as opposed to the “magic fraction” proposed by Kelly. Going all in, to use poker terminology, will maximize his expected total wealth, hence his expected utility, for any finite number of periods.24 In short, Samuelson shows that the Kelly Criterion, though mathematically correct, should not guide an

investor’s actions, since it ignores the structure of preferences, whether risk neutral or risk averse.25
Accounting for preferences, it turns out that the Kelly Criterion leads to precisely the right investment proportions if one’s utility function is logarithmic, but it is too conservative for less risk-averse utility functions, and vice versa.  With logarithmic utility, one will just take an even money bet that either multiplies one’s wealth by 1+x or by 1/(1+x), for any x. Thus, one would take an even money bet to double or halve one’s wealth.

I lack both the space and capability to straighten out the sequential investment problem. But I should make a few observations to point out that even if the Kelly Criterion were correct, the formulation it employs does not capture most real world investment opportunities: (1) Most UU investments are illiquid for a significant period, often of unknown length. Monies invested today will not be available for reinvestment until they become liquid. (2) Markets charge enormous premiums to cash out illiquid assets.26 (3) Models of  optimal  sequential investment strategies tend to assume away the most important real- world challenges to such strategies, such as uncertain lock-in periods. (4) There are substantial disagreements in the literature even about “toy problems,” such as those with immediate resolution of known-probability investments. The overall conclusion is that: (5) Money management is a challenging task in UU problems. It afflicts even those with a substantial edge when making such investments. And when the unknowable happens, as it did with the air- pocket plunge in the 1987 stock market or the 1997 Asian crisis, unforeseen short-term money-management problems – e.g., transferring monies across markets in time to beat margin calls – tend to emerge. These five points imply that even if it were clear how one should invest in a string of favorable gambles each of which is resolved instantaneously, that would help us little in the real world of UU investing, which presents a much more difficult task.

Though I have quibbled about the Kelly Criterion, it makes a simple, central point that is missed in virtually all investment advice. Most such advice focuses on efficient or near efficient markets, implying that one will not have a great edge in any investment. In contrast, the real world presents some ordinary investments, some attractive investments, and some very attractive investments. Clearly it makes sense to invest more in the more attractive investments. This leads to a maxim on investment advantage:

Maxim B: The greater is your expected return on an investment, that is the larger is your advantage, the greater the percentage of your capital you should put at risk.

Most investors understand this criterion intuitively, at least once it is pointed out. But they follow it insufficiently if at all. The investment on which they expect a 30% return gets little more funding than the one where they expect to earn 10%. Investment advantage should be as important as diversification concerns in determining how one distributes one’s portfolio.


IV. INVESTING WITH SOMEONE ON THE OTHER SIDE

One of the more puzzling aspects of the financial world is the volume of transactions in international currency markets. Average daily volume is $1.9 trillion, which is slightly more than all U.S. imports in a year. There are hedgers in these markets, to be sure, but their volume is many times dwarfed by transactions that cross with sophisticated or at least highly paid traders on both sides. Something no less magical than levitation is enabling all players to make money, or think that they are making money.

But let us turn to the micro situation, where you are trading against a single individual in what may or may not be a UU situation. If we find that  people make severe mistakes in this arena even when there is merely risk or uncertainty, we should be much more concerned, at least for them, when UU may abound.

Bazerman-Samuelson example and lessons. Let us posit that you are 100% sure that an asset is worth more to you than to the person who holds it, indeed 50% more. But assume that she knows the true value to her, and that it is uniformly distributed on [0,100], that is, her value is equally likely to be 0, 1, 2, … 100. In a famous game due to Bazerman and Samuelson (1983), hereafter BS, you are to make a single bid. She will accept if she gets more than her own value. What should you bid?

When asked in the classroom, typical bids will be 50 or 60, and few will bid as low as 20. Students reason that the item will be worth 50 on average to her, hence 75 to them. They bid to get a tidy profit. The flaw in the reasoning is that the seller will only accept if she will make a profit. Let’s make you the bidder. If you offer 60, she will not sell if her value exceeds 60. This implies that her average value conditional on selling will be 30, which is the value of the average number from 0 to 60. Your expected value will be 1.5 times this amount, or 45. You will lose 15 on average, namely 60-45, when your bid is accepted. It is easy to show that any positive bid loses money in expectation. The moral of this story is that people, even people in decision analysis and finance classrooms, where these experiments have been run many times, are very poor at taking account of the decisions of people on the other side of the table.

There is also a strong tendency to draw the wrong inference from this example, once its details are explained. Many people conclude that you should never deal with someone else who knows the true value, when you know only the distribution. In fact, BS offer an extreme example, almost the equivalent of an optical illusion. You might conclude that when your information is very diffuse and the other side knows for sure, you should not trade even if you have a strong absolute advantage.

That conclusion is wrong. For example, if the seller’s true value  is uniform on [1,2] and you offer 2, you will buy the object for sure, and its expected value will be 1.5 times 1.5 = 2.25. The difference between this example and the one with the prior on [0,1] is that here the effective information discrepancy is much smaller. To see this, think of a uniform distribution from [100,101]; there is virtually no discrepancy. (In fact, bidding 2 is the optimal bid for the [1,2] example, but that the extreme bid is optimal also should not be generalized.)

Drawing inferences from others. The general lesson is that people are naturally very poor at drawing inferences from the fact that there is a willing seller on the other side of the market. Our instincts and early training lead us not to trust the other guy, because his interests so frequently diverge from ours. If someone is trying to convince you that his second hand car is wondrous, skepticism and valuing your own information highly helps. However, in their study of the heuristics that individuals employ to help them make decisions, Tversky and Kahneman (1974) discovered that individuals tend to extrapolate heuristics from situations where they make sense to those where they do not.

For example, we tend to distrust the other guy’s information even when he is on our side. This tendency has serious drawbacks if you consider sidecar investing – free riding on the superior capability of others – as we do below. Consider two symmetrically-situated partners with identical interests who start with an identical prior distribution about some value which is described by a two- parameter distribution. They each get some information on the value. They also have identical prior distributions on the information that each will receive. Thus, after his draw, each has a posterior mean and variance. Their goal is to take a decision whose payoff will depend on the true value. The individuals begin by submitting their best estimate, namely their means. After observing each other’s means, they then simultaneously submit their new best estimate. Obviously, if  one had a tight (loose) posterior his estimate would shift more (less) toward that of his partner. In theory, two things should happen: 

(a) The two partners should jump over each other between the first and second submission half of the time.

(b) The two partners should give precisely the same estimate for the third submission.

In practice, unless the players are students of Robert Aumann27 – his article “Agreeing to Disagree” (1976) inspired this example – rarely will they jump over each other. Moreover, on the third submission, they will not come close to convergence.

The moral of this story is that we are deeply inclined to trust our own information more than that of a counterpart, and are not well trained to know when this makes good sense, and when it inclines us to be a sucker. One should also be on the lookout for information disparities. Rarely are they revealed through carnival-barker behavior. For example, when a seller merely offers you an object at a price, or gets to accept or reject when you make a bid (as with BS), he will utilize information that you do not possess. You had better be alert and give full weight to its likely value, e.g., how much the object is worth on average were he to accept your bid.

In the financial world one is always playing in situations where the other fellow may have more information and you must be on your guard. But unless you have a strictly dominant action – i.e., it is superior no matter what the other guy’s information -- a maximin strategy will almost always push you never to invest. After all, his information could be just such to lead you to lose large amounts of money.

Two rays of light creep into this gloomy situation: First, only rarely will his information put you at severe disadvantage. Second, it is extremely unlikely that your counterpart is playing anything close to an optimal strategy. After all, if it is so hard for you to analyze, it can hardly be easy for him.28
  
Absolute advantage and information asymmetry. It is helpful to break down these situations into two components. A potential buyer’s absolute advantage benefits both players. It represents the usual gains from trade. In many  financial situations, as we observed above, a buyer’s absolute advantage stems from her complementary skills. An empty lot in A’s hands may be worth much less than it would be in B’s. Both gain if A trades to B, due to absolute advantage. But such an argument would not apply if A was speculating that the British pound would fall against the dollar when B was speculating that it would rise. There is no absolute advantage in such a situation, only information asymmetries.

If both parties recognize a pure asymmetric information situation, only the better informed player should participate. The appropriate drawing of inferences of “what- you-know-since-you-are-willing-to-trade” should lead to the well known no-trade equilibrium. Understanding this often leads even ordinary  citizens to a shrewd strategem:

Maxim C: When information asymmetries may lead your counterpart to be concerned about trading with you, identify for her important areas where you  have an absolute advantage from trading. You can also identify her absolute advantages, but she is more likely to know those already.

When you are the buyer, beware; seller-identified absolute advantages can be chimerical. For example, the seller in the bazaar is good at explaining why your special characteristics deserve a money-losing price – say it is the end of the day and he needs money to take home to his wife. The house seller who does not like the traffic noise in the morning may palter that he is moving closer to his job, suggesting absolute advantage since that is not important to you. Stores in tourist locales are always having “Going Out of Business Sales.” Most swindles operate because the swindled one thinks he is in the process of getting a steal deal from someone else.

If a game theorist had written a musical comedy, it would have been Guys and Dolls, filled as it is with the ploys and plots of small-time gamblers. The overseer of the roving craps game is Nathan Detroit. He is seeking action, and asks Sky Masterson – whose good looks and gambling success befit his name – to bet on yesterday’s cake sales at Lindy’s, a famed local deli. Sky declines and recounts a story to Nathan:

On the day when I left home to make my way in the world, my daddy took me to one side. “Son,” my daddy says to me, “I am sorry I am not able to bankroll you to a large start, but not having the necessary lettuce to get you rolling, instead I'm going to stake you to some very valuable advice. One of these days in your travels, a guy is going to show you a brand-new deck of cards on which the seal is not yet broken. Then this guy is going to offer to bet you that he can make the jack of spades jump out of this brand-new deck of cards and squirt cider in your ear. But, son, do not accept this bet, because as sure as you stand there, you're going to wind up with an ear full of cider.”

In the financial world at least, a key consideration in dealing with UU situations is assessing what others are likely to know or not know. You are unlikely to have mystical powers to foresee the unforeseeable, but you may be able to estimate your understanding relative to that of others. Sky’s dad drew an inference from someone else’s willingness to bet. Presumably Ricardo was not a military expert, but just understood that bidders would be few and that the market would overdiscount the UU risk.

Competitive knowledge, uncertainty, and ignorance. Let us assume that you are neither the unusually skilled Buffett nor the unusually clear-thinking Ricardo. You are just an ordinary investor who gets opportunities and information from time to time. Your first task is to decide into which box an investment decision would fall. We start with unknown probabilities.

Investing with Uncertainty and Potential Asymmetric Information



Easy for Others to Estimate
Hard for Others to Estimate
Easy for You to Estimate
A. Tough markets
B. They’re the Sucker
Hard for You to Estimate
C. Sky Masterson’s Dad, You’re the Sucker
D. Buffett’s Reinsurance Sale Calif. Earthquake Auth.

The first row is welcome and relatively easy, for two reasons: 

(1) You probably have reasonable judgment of your knowledge relative to others, as would a major real estate developer considering deals in his home market. Thus you would have a good assessment of how likely you are to be in Box B or Box A. 

(2) If you are in Box B, you have the edge. Box A is the home of the typical thick financial market, where we tend to think prices are fair on average.

The second row is more interesting, and brings us to the subject matter of this paper. In Part V below, we will see Buffett sell a big hunk of reinsurance because he knew he was in box D. His premium was extremely favorable, and he knew that the likelihood of extreme odds-shifting information being possessed by the other side was thin. Box C consists of situations where you know little, and others may know a fair amount. The key to successfully dealing with situations where you find probabilities hard to estimate is to be able to assess whether others might be finding it easy.

Be sensitive to telling signs that the other side knows more, such as a smart person offering too favorable odds. Indeed, if another sophisticated party is willing to bet, and he can’t know that you find probabilities hard to estimate, you should be suspicious. For he should have reasonable private knowledge so as to protect himself. The regress in such reasoning is infinite.

Maxim D: In a situation where probabilities may be hard for either side to assess, it may be sufficient to assess your knowledge relative to the party on the other side (perhaps the market).

Let us now turn to the more extreme case, situations where even the states of the world are unknown, as they would be for an angel investment in a completely new technology, or for insuring infrastructure against terrorism over a long period.

Investing with Ignorance and Potential Asymmetric Information



Known to Others
Unknown to Others
Unknown to You
E. Dangerous Waters Monday Morning Quarterback Risk
F. Low Competition Monday Morning Quarterback Risk

In some ignorance situations, you may be confident that others know no better. That would place you in Box F, a box where most investors get deterred, and where the Buffetts of this world, and the Rothschilds of yesteryear have made lots of money. Investors are deterred because they employ a heuristic to stay  away from UU situations, because they might be in E, even though a careful assessment would tell them that outcome was highly unlikely. In addition, both boxes carry the Monday Morning Quarterback (MMQ) risk; one might be blamed for a poor outcome if one invests in ignorance, when it was a good decision that got a bad outcome; might not have allowed for the fact that others might have had better knowledge when in fact they didn’t; or might not have allowed for the fact that others might have had better knowledge, when in fact they did, but that negative was outweighed by the positive of your absolute advantage. The criticisms are unmerited. But since significant losses were incurred, and knowledge was scant, the investment looks foolish in retrospect to all but the most sophisticated. An investor who could suffer significantly from any of these critiques might well be deterred from investing.

Let us revisit the Gazprom lesson within this thought in mind. Suppose you are a Russia expert. It is still almost inevitable that real Russians know much more than you. What then should you do? The prudent course, it would seem, would be first to determine your MMQ risk. It may actually be reduced due to your largely irrelevant expertise. But if MMQ is considerable, steer clear. If not, and Russian insiders are really investing, capitalize on Box E, and make that sidecar investment. You have the additional advantage that few Westerners will be doing the same, and they are your prime competition for ADRs.29

Speculation 3. UU situations offer great investment potential given the combination of information asymmetries and lack of competition.

Boxes E and F are also the situations where other players will be attempting to take advantage of us and, if it is our inclination, we might take advantage of them. This is the area where big money changes hands.

A key problem is to determine when you might be played for a sucker. Sometimes this is easy. Anyone who has small oil interests will have received many letters offering to buy, no doubt coming from people offering far less than fair value. They are monopsonists after all, and appropriately make offers well below the market. They may not even have any inside knowledge. But they are surely taking advantage of the impulsive or impatient among us, or those who do not understand the concepts in this paper.

Being a possible sucker may be an advantage if you can gauge the probability. People are strongly averse to being betrayed. They demand much stronger odds when a betraying human rather than an indifferent nature would be the cause of a loss (Bohnet and Zeckhauser, 2004). Given that, where betrayal is  a risk, potential payoffs will be too high relative to what rational decision analysis would prescribe.

Investing in UU with potentially informed players on the other side. Though you may confront a UU situation, the party or parties on the other side may be well informed. Usually you will not know whether they are. Gamblers opine that if  you do not know who the sucker is in a game that you are the sucker. That does not automatically apply with UU investments. First, the other side may also be uninformed. For example, if you buy a partially completed shopping center, it may be that the developer really did run out of money (the proffered explanation for its status) as opposed to his discovery of deep tenant reluctance. Second, you may have a complementary skill, e.g., strong relations with WalMart, that may give you a significant absolute advantage multiple.

The advantage multiple versus selection formula. Let us simplify and leave risk aversion and money management matters aside. Further posit, following BS, that you are able to make a credible take-it-or-leave-it offer of 1. The value of the asset to him is v, an unknown quantity. The value to you is av, where a is your absolute advantage. Your subjective prior probability distribution on v is f (v).  The mean value of your prior is m < 1.30 In a stripped-down model, three parameters describe this situation: your advantage multiple, a; the probability that the other side is informed, p; and the selection factor against you, s, if the other side is informed.31 Thus s is the fraction of expected value that will apply, on average, if the other side is informed, and therefore only sells when the asset has low value to her. Of course, given the UU situation, you do not know s, but you should rely on your mean value of your subjective distribution for that parameter.

If you knew p = 0, that the other side knew no more than you, you would simply make the offer if am > 1. If you knew there were selection, i.e., p = 1, you would invest if your multiple more than compensated for selection, namely if ams
> 1. The general formula is that your return will be:

am[ps + (1-p)1] .                                                                     (1)

Maxim E: A significant absolute advantage offers some protection against potential selection. You should invest in a UU world if your advantage multiple  is great, unless the probability is high the other side is informed and if, in addition, the expected selection factor is severe.

Following Maxim E, you should make your offer when the expression in (1) exceeds 1.

In practice, you will have a choice of offer, t. Thus, s will vary with t, i.e., s(t).32 The payoff for any t will be

If at the optimal offer t*, this quantity is positive, you should offer t*.

Playing the advantage multiple versus selection game. Our formulation posited a take-it-or-leave-it offer with no communication. In fact, most important financial exchanges have rounds of subtle back-and-forth discussion. This is not simply cheap talk. Sometimes real information is provided, e.g., accounting statements, geological reports, antique authentications. And offers by each side reveal information as well. Players on both sides know that information asymmetry is an enemy to both, as in any agency problem.

It is well known that if revealed information can be verified, and if the buyer knows on what dimensions information will be helpful, then by an unraveling argument all information gets revealed.33 Consider a one-dimension case where a value can be between 1 and 100. A seller with a 100 would surely reveal, implying the best unrevealed information would be 99. But then the 99 would reveal, and so on down through 2.

When the buyer is in a UU situation, unraveling does not occur, since he does not know the relevant dimensions. The seller will keep private unfavorable information on dimensions unknown to the buyer. She will engage in  signposting: announcing favorable information, suppressing unfavorable.34

The advantage multiple versus selection game will usually proceed with the seller explaining why she does not have private information, or revealing private information indicating that m and a are large. Still, many favorable deals will not get done, because the less informed party can not assess what it does not know. Both sides lose ex ante when there will be asymmetry on common value information, or when, as in virtually all UU situations, asymmetry is suspected.

Auctions as UU games. Auctions have exploded as mechanisms to sell everything from the communications spectrum to corporate securities. Economic analyses of auctions – how to conduct them and how to bid – have exploded alongside. The usual prescription is that the seller should reveal his information about elements that will affect all buyers’ valuations, e.g., geologic information on an oil lease or evidence of an antique’s pedigree, to remove buyers’ concerns about the Winner’s Curse. The Winner’s Curse applies when an object, such as an oil lease, is worth roughly the same to all. The high bidder should be aware that every other bidder thought it was worth less than he did. Hence, his estimate is too high, and he is cursed for winning.

Real world auctions are often much more complex. Even the rules of the game may not be known. Consider the common contemporary auction phenomenon, witnessed often with house sales in hot markets, and at times with the sale of corporations.35 The winner, who expected the final outcome to have been determined after one round of bidding, may be told there will be a best and final offer round, or that now she can negotiate a deal for the item.

Usually the owner of the object establishes the rules of the game. In theory, potential buyers would insist that they know the rules. In practice, they often have not. When Recovery Engineering, makers of PUR water purifiers, was sold in 1999, a “no one knows the rules” process ensued, with Morgan Stanley representing the seller. A preliminary auction was held on an August Monday. Procter and Gamble (P&G) and Gillette bid, and a third company expressed interest but said it had difficulties putting its bid together. Gillette’s bid was $27 per share; P&G’s was $22. P&G was told by the investment banker that it would have to improve its bid substantially. Presumably, Gillette was told little, but drew appropriate inferences, namely that it was by far high. The final auction was scheduled for that Friday at noon. Merrill Lynch, Gillette’s investment banker, called early on Friday requesting a number of additional pieces of due diligence information, and requesting a delay till Monday. Part of the information was released – Gillette had had months to request it – and the auction was delayed till 5 p.m. Friday. P&G bid $34. At 5 p.m., Merrill Lynch called, desperate, saying it could not get in touch with Gillette. Brief extensions were granted, but contact could not be established. P&G was told that it was the high bidder. Over the weekend a final deal was negotiated at a slightly higher price; the $300 million deal concluded. But would there have been a third round of auction if Gillette had bid $33.50 that Friday? No one knows.

The Recovery board puzzled over the unknowable question: What happened to Gillette? One possibility was that Gillette inferred from the fact that it was not told its Monday bid was low that it was in fact way above other bidders. It was simply waiting for a deal to be announced, and then would propose a price perhaps $2 higher, rather than bid and end up $5 higher.36 Gillette never came back. A while later, Recovery learned that Gillette was having – to that time unreported – financial difficulties. Presumably, at the moment of truth Gillette concluded that it was not the time to purchase a new business. In short, this was a game of unknowable rules, and unknowable strategies.37 Not unusual.

At the close of 2005, Citigroup made the winning bid of about $3 billion for 85% of the Guangdong Development Bank, a financially troubled state-owned Chinese bank. As the New York Times reported the deal, it “won the right to negotiate with the bank to buy the stake.” If successful there, its “control might allow Citigroup to install some new management and have some control over the bank’s future…one of the most destitute of China’s big banks…overrun by bad loans.”38 Citigroup is investing in a UU situation, and knows that both the rules  of the game and what it will win are somewhat undefined. But it is probably confident that other bidders were no better informed, and that both the bank and the Chinese government (which must approve the deal) may also not know the value of the bank, and were eager to secure foreign control. Great value may come from buying a pig in a poke, if others also can not open the bag.

Ideal investments with high and low payoffs. In many UU situations, even the events associated with future payoff levels – for example, whether a technology supplier produces a breakthrough or a new product emerges – are hard to foresee. The common solution in investment deals is to provide for distributions of the pie that depend not on what actually happens, but solely on money received. This would seem to simplify matters, but even in such situations sophisticated investors frequently get confused.

With venture capital in high tech, for example, it is not uncommon for those providing the capital to have a contractual claim to all the assets should the venture go belly up. Similarly, “cram down” financings, which frequently follow when startups underperform, often gives VCs a big boost in ownership share. In theory, such practices could provide strong incentives to the firm’s managers. In reality, the managers’ incentives are already enormous. Typical VC arrangements given bad outcomes cause serious ill will, and distort incentives – for example, they reward gambling behavior by managers after a bleak streak. Worse still for the VCs, they are increasing their share of the company substantially when the company is not worth much. They might do far better if arrangements specified that they sacrifice ownership share if matters turn out poorly, but gain share if the firm does particularly well.

Maxim F: In UU situations, even sophisticated investors tend to underweight how strongly the value of assets varies. The goal should be to get good payoffs when the value of assets is high.

No doubt Ricardo also took Maxim F into account when he purchased the “Waterloo bonds.” He knew that English money would be far more valuable if Wellington was victorious and his bonds soared in value, than if he lost and the bonds plummeted.

A UU investment problem. Now for a harder decision. Look at the letter in Exhibit A, which offers you the chance to make a modest investment in an oil well. You have never heard of Davis Oil and the letter came out of the blue, but you inquire and find out that it is the company previously owned by the famous, recently deceased oilman Marvin Davis. Your interest is offered because the Davis Company bought the managing partner’s interest in the prospect from a good friend and oil man who invited you into his prospect.39 Davis is legally required to make this offer to you. Decide whether to invest or merely wait for your costless override before you read on.

 
Here is what your author did. He started by assessing the situation. Davis could not exclude him, and clearly did not need his modest investment. The letter provided virtually no information, and was not even put on letterhead, presumably the favored Davis approach if it were trying to discourage investment. Davis had obviously spent a fair amount of effort determining whether to drill the well, and decided to go ahead. It must think its prospects were good, and you would be investing as a near partner.

Bearing this in mind, he called Bill Jaqua – a contact Davis identified in the letter – and asked about the well. He was informed it was a pure wildcat, and that it was impossible to guess the probability of success. Some geologic  technical discussion followed, which he tried to pretend he understood. He then asked what percent of Davis wildcat wells had been successful in recent years, and got a number of 20-25%. He then asked what the payoff was on average if  the wells were successful. The answer was 10 to 1. Beyond that, if this well was successful, there would be a number of other wells drilled in the field. Only participation now would give one the right to be a future partner, when presumably the odds would be much more favorable. This appeared to be a reasonably favorable investment, with a healthy upside option of future wells attached. The clinching argument was that Jaqua courteously explained that Davis would be happy to take his interest and give him the free override, thus reinforcing the message of the uninformative letter not placed on letterhead. (It turned out that the override would have only been 1% of revenue -- an amount not mentioned in the letter – as opposed to 76% if he invested.)40 In short, the structure of the situation, and the nature of Davis’s play made a sidecar investment imperative. The well has not yet been started.

Davis was in a tough situation. It had to invite in undesired partners on favorable terms when it had done all the work. It reversed the usual ploy where someone with a significant informational advantage tries to play innocent or worse, invoke some absolute advantage story. Davis tried to play up the UU aspect of the situation to discourage participation.

Review of the bidding. You have been asked to address some decision problems.  Go back now and grade yourself first on the overconfidence questionnaire. The answers are in the footnote.41

You were asked about three investments: Tengion, Gazprom and Davis Oil. Gazprom has done nicely over a six-month period. Neither of the other outcomes has been determined. Go back and reconsider your choices, and decide whether you employed the appropriate principles when making them, and then assess the more general implications for investment in UU situations. Though this essay pointed out pitfalls with UU investing, it was generally upbeat about the potential profits that reside in UU arenas. Hopefully you have been influenced, at least a bit.


V. A BUFFETT TALE

The following story encapsulates the fear of UU situations, even by sophisticated investors, and the potential for shrewd investors to take great advantage of such situations. In 1996, I was attending an NBER conference on insurance. One participant was the prime consultant to the California Earthquake Authority. He had been trying to buy a $1 billion slice of reinsurance – to take effect after $5 billion in aggregate insured losses -- from the New York financial community. The Authority was offering five times estimated actuarial value, but had no takers. It seemed exceedingly unlikely that the parties requesting coverage had inside information that a disastrous earthquake was likely. Hence, there was a big advantage, in effect a = 5, and p was close to 0. Maxim E – weigh absolute advantage against informational disadvantage – surely applied.

My dinner table syndicate swung into action, but ended up $999.9 million short. A couple days later, we learned that Buffett had flown to California to take the entire slice. Here is his explanation.

…we wrote a policy for the California Earthquake Authority that goes into effect on April 1, 1997, and that exposes us to a loss more than  twice that possible under the Florida contract. Again we retained all the risk for our own account. Large as these coverages are, Berkshire's after- tax "worst-case" loss from a true mega-catastrophe is probably no more than $600 million, which is less than 3% of our book value and 1.5% of our market value. To gain some perspective on this exposure, look at the table on page 2 and note the much greater volatility that security markets have delivered us. [Chairman’s letter to the Shareholders of Berkshire Hathaway, 1996, http://www.ifa.com/Library/Buffet.html]42


Reinsurance for earthquakes is certainly a venture into the unknown, but had many attractive features beyond its dramatic overpricing. Unlike most insurance, it was exceedingly unlikely that the parties taking insurance had inside knowledge on their risk. Thus, Buffett – despite attention to money management -- was willing to take 100% of a risk of which Wall Street firms houses rejected taking even part. Those fancy financial entities were not well equipped to take a risk on something that was hard for them to estimate. Perhaps they did not recognize that others had no inside information, that everyone was operating with the same probability. And perhaps they were just concerned about Monday Morning Quarterbacking.

It is also instructive to consider Buffett’s approach to assessing the probabilities in this UU situation, as revealed in the same annual report:

So what are the true odds of our having to make a payout during the policy's term? We don't know - nor do we think computer models will help us, since we believe the precision they project is a chimera. In fact, such models can lull decision-makers into a false sense of security and thereby increase their chances of making a really huge mistake. We've already seen such debacles in both insurance and investments. Witness "portfolio insurance," whose destructive effects in the 1987 market crash led one wag to observe that it was the computers that should have been jumping out of windows.

Buffett was basically saying to Wall Street firms: “Even if you hire 100 brilliant Ph.D.s to run your models, no sensible estimate will emerge.” These are precisely the types of UU situations where the competition will be thin, the odds likely favorable, and the Buffetts of this world can thrive.

As Buffett has shown on repeated occasions, a multi-billionaire will rush in where mathematical wizards fear to tread. Indeed, that explains much of his success. In 2006 hurricane insurance met two Buffett desiderata, high prices and reluctant competitors. So he plunged into the market:

Buffett’s prices are as much as 20 times higher than the rates prevalent a year ago, said Kevin Madden, an insurance broker at Aon Corp. in New York. On some policies, premiums equal half of its maximum potential payout, he said. [In a May 7, 2006, interview Buffett said:] “We will do more than anybody else if the price is right… We are certainly willing to lose $6 billion on a single event. I hope we don’t.'’ http://seekingalpha.com/article/11697

At least two important lessons emerge from thinking about the “advantage-versus-

Maxim G: Discounting for ambiguity is a natural tendency that should be overcome, just as should be overeating.

Maxim H: Do not engage in the heuristic reasoning that just because you do not know the risk, others do. Think carefully, and assess whether they are likely to know more than you. When the odds are extremely favorable, sometimes it pays to gamble on the unknown, even though there is some chance that people on the other side may know more than you.

Buffett took another bold financial move in 2006, in a quite different field, namely philanthropy. He announced that he would give away 85% of his fortune or $37.4 billion, with $31 billion going to the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation. Putting money with the Gates Foundation represents sidecar philanthropy. The Foundation is an extremely effective organization that focuses on health care and learning. It is soon to be led by Bill Gates, a fellow with creativity, vision and hardheadedness as strong complementary skills, skills which are as valuable in philanthropy as they are in business.

VI. CONCLUSION

This essay offers more speculations than conclusions, and provides anecdotal accounts rather than definitive data. Its theory is often tentative and implicit. But the question it seeks to answer is clear: How can one invest rationally in UU situations? The question sounds almost like an oxymoron. Yet clear thinking about UU situations, which includes prior diagnosis of their elements, and relevant practice with simulated situations, may vastly improve investment decisions where UU events are involved. If they do improve, such clear thinking will yield substantial benefits. For financial decisions at least, the benefits may be far greater than are available in run-of-the-mill contexts, since competition may be limited and prices well out of line.

How important are UU events in the great scheme of financial affairs? That itself is a UU question. But if we include only those that primarily affect individuals, the magnitude is far greater than what our news accounts would suggest. Learning to invest more wisely in a UU world may be the most promising way to significantly bolster your prosperity.

  
APPENDIX A

Assessing Quantities*


1.  Democratic votes in Montana, 2004 Presidential election
                                              2.    Length of Congo River (in miles)
                                              3.    Number of subscribers to Field and Stream
                                         4.    Area of Finland (in square miles)
                                         5.    Birth rate in France per 1,000 population
                                         6.    Population of Cambodia
                                         7.    Revenues of Wal-Mart Stores (largest in U.S.), 2003
8.  Annual Percent Yields on 30-Year Treasury Bonds   in 1981 (This year had the highest rate over the 1980-1998 period.)
                                         9.    Number of physicians in the United States, 2002
10.  Number of electoral votes going to Republican presidential candidate in 2008 (out of 538)
11.  Value of Dow Jones Average on December 31, 2006 (on 6/30/06 closed at 11,150)
12.  Value of the NASDAQ on December 31, 2006 (on 6/30/06 closed at 2,172)


1st %ile
25th %ile
50th %ile
75th %ile
99th %ile
Democratic votes MT
2004 Pres. election





Congo River
(length in miles)





Field & Stream (number
of subscribers)





Finland
(area in square miles)





Birth Rate of France
(per thousand)





Population of     Cambodia





Revenues of Wal-Mart
Stores, 2003





% Yields on
30-Year Bonds, 1981





Number of Physicians in
U.S., 2002





# electoral college votes,
Republican presidential candidate in 2008





Dow Jones Average 12/31/06
(on 6/30/06 closed at 11,150)





Value of NASDAQ 12/31/06
(on 6/30/06 closed at 2,172)





* Question 1, http://www.uselectionatlas.org/RESULTS/state.php?f=0&year=2004&fips=30. Questions 2-6, 1995 Information Please Almanac. Question 8, 1999 Wall Street Journal Almanac. Questions 7 & 9, World Almanac 2005.




                                     Remarks:
I thank Miriam Avins, Paul Samuelson and Nils Wernerfelt for helpful comments.

1 The financing of 36 million pounds was floated on the London Stock Exchange. Ricardo took a substantial share. His frequent correspondent Thomas Malthus took 5,000 pounds on Ricardo’s recommendation, but sold out shortly before news of the Waterloo outcome was received. The evidence is clear that Ricardo, in his words, understood the “dismal forebodings” of the situation, including “its consequences, on our [England’s] finances.” See Sraffa (1952, Vol VI, pp. 202, 229 and surrounding material.

2 Ralph Gomory’s (1995) literary essay on the Unknown and Unknowable provided inspiration. Miriam Avins provided helpful comments.

3 The classic description of uncertainty, a situation where probabilities could not be known, is due to Frank Knight (1921).

4 This is sometimes expressed that things move geometrically rather than arithmetically, or that the logarithm of price has a traditional symmetric distribution. The most studied special case is the lognormal distribution. See “Life is log-normal” by E. Limpert and W. Stahel, http://www.inf.ethz.ch/personal/gut/lognormal/brochure.html, for an argument on the widespread applicability of this distribution.

5 Ricardo’s major competitors were the Baring Brothers and the Rothschilds. Do not feel sorry for the Rothschilds. In the 14 years from 1814 to 1828 they multiplied their money 8-fold, often betting on UU situations, while the Baring Brothers lost capital. http://www.businessweek.com/1998/49/b3607071.htm. Analysis based on Niall Ferguson’s  House of Rothschild.

6 Hart and Tauman (2004) show that market crashes are possible purely due to information processing among market participants, with no new information.  They observe that the 1987  crash – 20% in a day – happened despite no new important information becoming available, nor negative economic performance after the crash. Market plunges due to ordinary information processing defies any conventional explanation, and is surely a UU event.

7 Nassim Taleb and Benoit Mandelbrot posit that many financial phenomena are distributed according to a power law, implying that the relative likelihood of movements of different sizes depends only on their ratio. Thus, a 20% market drop relative to a 10% drop is the same as a 10% drop relative to a 5%  drop.  http://www.fooledbyrandomness.com/fortune.pdf.  Power distributions have fat tails. In their empirical studies, economists frequently assume that  deviations from predicted values have normal distributions. That makes computations tractable, but evidence suggests that tails are often much thicker than with the normal. Zeckhauser and Thompson (1970).

8 Complementary skills can also help the less affluent invest.  Miriam Avins, a good friend,  moved into an edgy neighborhood in Baltimore because the abandoned house next door looked like a potential community garden, she knew she had the skills to move the project forward, and she valued the learning experience the house would bring to her family. Her house value doubled in 3 years, and her family learned as well.

9 Dinner speech to annual executive program on Investment Decisions and Behavioral Finance, John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University, October 14, 2004.


10 This investment was proposed when this paper was presented at a conference sponsored by the Wharton School on January 6, 2006. The price was then 33.60. At press time nine months later it was $47.


12 Approximate average from Investment Decisions and Behavioral Finance, executive program, annually fall 2001-2006, and API-302, Analytic Frameworks for Policy course. The former is chaired, the latter taught by Richard Zeckhauser, Kennedy School, Harvard University.

13 See Gilbert (2006) for insightful discussions of the problems of rationalization and corrigibility.

14 See Viscusi and Zeckhauser (2005).

15Kahneman and Tversky (1979).

16 This illustration employs events that may have happened in the past, but subjects would not know. The purpose is to make payoffs immediate, since future payoffs suffer from a different  form of bias.

17 The experiment is at a disadvantage in getting this result, since peoples’ assessments of the contingencies’ probabilities would vary widely. Some would pick D because they attached an unusually high probability to it. In theory, one could ask people their probability estimate after they made their choice, and then look only at the answers of those for whom the probability was in a narrow range. However, individuals would no doubt adjust their retrospective probability estimates to help rationalize their choice.
  
18 This experiment and the choice between lotteries C and D above only approximate those with numerical probabilities, since they are calibrated for median responses and individuals’ estimates will differ.

19 In fact, Ellsberg’s experiment involved drawing a marble of a particular color from an urn. Subjects preferred a situation where the percentage of winning marbles was known, even if they could bet on either side when it was unknown.

20 Fox and Tversky (1995, p. 585) found that ambiguity aversion was “produced by a comparison with less ambiguous events or with more knowledgeable people….[it] seems to disappear in a noncomparative context.” Ambiguity aversion is still relevant for investments, if alternative investments are available and contemplated.

21 Paul Samuelson, who attends closely to most aspects of the finance field, attests to this challenge. He observed that the Renaissance Group, run by former Stony Brook math professor Jim Simons, is “perhaps the only long-time phenomenal performer [in traditional financial markets] on a risk-corrected basis.” Private communication, June 15, 2006.

22I saw such path blazing by my former business partner Victor Niederhoffer in the 1970s, when he ventured into commodity investing. His associates hand recorded commodity prices at 15- minute intervals. He lined up a flotilla of TRS-80 Radio Shack computers to parallel process this information. His innovative data mining, spurred by accompanying theories of how markets behave, gave him a giant advantage over major investment houses. Niederhoffer continues along unusual paths, now making a second fortune after losing his first in the collapse of the Thai baht in 1997.
http://www.greenwichtime.com/business/scn-sa-black1jun18,0,3887361.story?page=5&coll=green-business-headlines

23 Samuelson, Paul A. (1979). “Why We Should Not Make Mean Log of Wealth Big Though Years to Act Are Long,” Journal of Baking and Finance 3: 305-307.

24 http://www.investopedia.com/articles/trading/04/091504.asp. In an interesting coincidence, Elwyn Berlekamp, a distinguished Berkeley math professor who was Kelly’s research assistant, was an extremely successful investor in a brief stint managing a fund for Jim Simons. See  footnote 19.

25 In the language of decision theory, individuals who follow Kelly rather than maximizing expected utility would be making a sacrifice in the certainty equivalent value of their terminal wealth, i.e., the wealth that results after participating in a string of gambles. The Kelly criterion is appropriate for someone with a logarithmic utility function.

26 For example, in real estate, a limited partnership interest that will come due in a few years is likely to sell about 30% below discounted expected future value. The significant discount reflects the complementary skills of acquirers, who must be able to assess and unlock the value of idiosyncratic partnerships. Personal communication, Eggert Dagbjartsson, Equity Resource Investments, December 2005. That firm earns substantial excess returns through its combination of effective evaluation of UU situations, and the unusual complementary skill of being able to deal effectively with recalcitrant general partners. Experience with Dagbjartsson’s firm – with which the author is associated – helped inspire this paper.

27 Robert Aumann and Thomas Schelling won the 2005 Nobel Memorial Prize in Economics for their contributions to game theory.

28 Given the potential for imperfect play, it is sometimes dangerous to draw inferences from the play of others, particularly when their preferences are hard to read. The Iraqi weapons of mass destruction provide a salient example. Many people were confident that such weapons were present not because of intelligence, but because they believed Saddam Hussein could have saved himself and his regime simply by letting in inspectors, who in the instance would find nothing.

29 In January 2006, Gazprom traded in the west as an ADR, but soon became an over-the-counter stock.

30 It is important that m < 1. Otherwise the seller would refuse your offer if he were uninformed.

31 In health care, this process is called adverse selection, with sicker people tending to enroll in more generous health plans.

32 Let v be the conditional mean of x < v. The value of s will be constant if v/v = positive k for all v. This will be the case if f(v) is homogeneous, i.e., f(kv) = knf(v), as with the uniform or triangular distribution starting at 0.

33 See Grossman (1981) on unraveling. If information is costly to reveal, then less favorable information is held back and signposting applies (Zeckhauser and Marks, 1996).

34 To be sure, the shrewd buyer can deduce: “Given the number of unknown dimensions I suspected, the seller has revealed relatively few.” Hence, I assume that there are a number of unfavorable dimensions, etc. When seller revelation is brief, only high m buyers will make exchanges. The doubly shrewd buyer may be informed or get informed on some dimension without the seller knowing which. He can then say: “I have unfavorable information on a dimension. Unless you reveal on all dimensions, this information will stay private, and I will  know that you are suppressing information.” The triply shrewd buyer, knowing nothing, will  make the same statement. The shrewd seller has countermeasures, such as insisting on proof that the buyer is informed, e.g., by third party attestation, and if evidence is received then revealing some but not all, hoping to hit the lucky dimension.

35 See Subramanian and Zeckhauser (2004), who apply the term “negotiauctions” to such processes.

36 Recovery created a countermeasure to raise any post-deal bid by inserting a breakup fee in its deal with P&G that declined (ultimately to 0) with the price premium paid by a new buyer.

37 Details confirmed by Brian Sullivan, then CEO of Recovery Engineering, in personal communication, January 2006. Zeckhauser was on the Recovery board due to a sidecar privilege. He had been Sullivan’s teacher, and had gotten him the job.

38 New York Times, December 31, 2005, B1 and B4. Citigroup had several Chinese state-owned companies as partners, but they probably gave more political cover than knowledge of the value of the bank.

39 That man was Malcolm Brachman, president of Northwest Oil, a bridge teammate and close friend. Sadly Malcolm had died in the interim. One consequence was that he could not advise  you.

40 Not mentioned in the letter was that 24% went off the top to priority claims, and that Davis charges 75% if you take the free override.

41 1) 173,710 2) 2,716 3) 2,007,901 4) 130,119 5) 13 6) 12,212,000 7) $259B 8) 13.45% 9)
853,000, 10) 173, 11) 12,466, 12) 2,444


REFERENCES

Alpert, M. and Raiffa, H. (1982). “A Progress Report on the Training of Probability Assessors,” in Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, Kahneman, D., P. Slovic, and A. Tversky, (eds.), pp. 294-305. Cambridge University Press, New York.

Aumann, R. (1976). “Agreeing to Disagree,” Annals of Statistics 4: 1236-1239.

Bazerman, M. and Samuelson, W. (1983). “I Won the Auction But Don’t Want the Prize,” Journal of Conflict Resolution 27: 618-634.

Bohnet, I. and Zeckhauser, R. (2004). “Trust, Risk and Betrayal,” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 55: 467-484.

Ellsberg, D. (1961). “Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 75: 643-669.

Fox,   C.   and   Tversky, A.  (1995).  “Ambiguity Aversion and Comparative Ignorance,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 110(3): 585-603.
Gilbert, D. (2006). Stumbling on Happiness. Alfred A. Knopf, New York. Gomory,  R., (June 1995).   “An Essay on the Known, the Unknown and the
Unknowable,” Scientific American 272: 120.

Grossman, S.J. (1981). “The Informational Role of Warranties and Private Disclosure about Product Quality,” Journal of Law and Economics, 24(3): 461-483.

Hart,  S.  and  Tauman, Y. (2004).  “Market Crashes without External Shocks,”
Journal of Business 77(1): 1-8.

Kahneman,  D.  and  Tversky,  A.  (1979). “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk,” Econometrica 47, 263-291.
Knight, F. (2001). Risk, Uncertainty and Profit. Houghton Mifflin, Boston. Munger, C. (2005). Poor Charlie’s Almanack: The Wit and Wisdom of Charles

Raiffa, H. (1968). Decision Analysis.  Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA. Samuelson, P. (1979). “Why We Should Not Make Mean Log of Wealth Big
Though Years to Act Are Long,” Journal of Banking and Finance 3: 305-307.
Savage, L. J. (1954). The Foundations of Statistics. Wiley, New York. Sraffa, P. editor with M.H. Dobb (1952). The Works and Correspondence of
David Ricardo. Cambridge University Press: London.

Subramanian, G. and Zeckhauser, R. (2005). “‘Negotiauctions’: Taking a Hybrid Approach to the Sale of High Value Assets,” Negotiation 8(2): 4-6.

Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases,” Science 185: 1124-1131.

Viscusi, W.K. and Zeckhauser, R. (2005). “Recollection Bias and the Combat of Terrorism,” Journal of Legal Studies 34: 27-55.

Zeckhauser, R. and Thompson, M. (1970). “Linear Regression with Non-Normal Error Terms,” Review of Economics and Statistics 52(3): 280-286.

Zeckhauser, R. and Marks, D. (1996). “Signposting: The Selective Revelation of Product Information,” in Wise Choices: Games, Decisions, and Negotiations, Zeckhauser, R., R. Keeney, and J. Sebenius (eds.), pp. 22-
41. Harvard Business School Press, Boston.

Tuesday, December 3, 2019

Richard Koo, “The world in balance sheet recession: causes, cure, and politics”



Paper directly copied and posted from:
Richard Koo, “The world in balance sheet recession: causes, cure, and politics”, real-world economics review, issue no. 58, 12 December 2011, pp.19-37,


http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue58/Koo58.pdf
You may post and read comments on this paper at
http://rwer.wordpress.com/2011/12/12/rwer-issue-58-richard-koo/


Richard C. Koo (Nomura Research Institute, Tokyo)

A recurring concern in the Western economies today is that they may be headed toward a Japan-like lost decade. Remarkable similarities between house price movements in the U.S. this time and in Japan 15 years ago, illustrated in Exhibit 1, suggest that the two countries have indeed contracted a similar disease. The post-1990 Japanese experience, however, also demonstrated that the nation’s recession was no ordinary recession.


Recession driven by deleveraging leads to prolonged slump
The key difference between an ordinary recession and one that can produce a lost decade is that in the latter, a large portion of the private sector is actually minimizing debt instead of maximizing profits following the bursting of a nation-wide asset price bubble. When a debt-financed bubble bursts, asset prices collapse while liabilities remain, leaving millions of private sector balance sheets underwater. In order to regain their financial health and credit ratings, households and businesses are forced to repair their balance sheets by increasing savings or paying down debt. This act of deleveraging reduces aggregate demand and throws the economy into a very special type of recession.

The first casualty of this shift to debt minimization is monetary policy, the traditional remedy for recessions, because people with negative equity are not interested in increasing borrowing at any interest rate. Nor will there be many willing lenders for those with impaired balance sheets, especially when the lenders themselves have balance sheet problems. Moreover, the money supply, which consists mostly of bank deposits, contracts when the private sector collectively draws down bank deposits to repay debt. Although the central bank can inject liquidity into the banking system, it will be hard-pressed to reverse the shrinkage of bank deposits when there are no borrowers and the money multiplier is zero or negative at the margin.

As shown in Exhibits 2 and 3, massive injections of liquidity by both the Federal Reserve in the US and the Bank of England in the UK not only failed to prevent contractions in credit available to the private sector, but also produced only miniscule increases in the money supply. This is exactly what happened to Japan after the bursting of its bubble in 1990, as shown in Exhibit 4.

Nor is there any reason why bringing back inflation or inflation targeting should work, because people are paying down debt in response to the fall in asset prices, not consumer prices. And with the money multiplier negative at the margin, the central bank does not have the means to produce the money supply growth needed to increase the inflation rate.




More importantly, when the private sector deleverages in spite of zero interest rates, the economy enters a deflationary spiral because, in the absence of people borrowing and spending money, the economy continuously loses demand equal to the sum of savings and net debt repayments. This process will continue until either private sector balance sheets are repaired or the private sector has become too poor to save (i.e., the economy enters a depression).

To see this, consider a world where a household has an income of $1,000 and a savings rate of 10 percent. This household would then spend $900 and save $100. In the usual or textbook world, the saved $100 will be taken up by the financial sector and lent to a borrower who can best use the money. When that borrower spends the $100, aggregate expenditure totals $1,000 ($900 plus $100) against original income of $1,000, and the economy moves on. When demand for the $100 in savings is insufficient, interest rates are lowered, which usually prompts a borrower to take up the remaining sum. When demand is excessive, interest rates are raised, prompting some borrowers to drop out.

In the world where the private sector is minimizing debt, however, there are no borrowers for the saved $100 even with interest rates at zero, leaving only $900 in expenditures. That $900 represents someone’s income, and if that person also saves 10 percent, only $810 will be spent. Since repairing balance sheets after a major bubble bursts typically takes many years—15 years in the case of Japan—the saved $90 will go un-borrowed again, and the economy will shrink to $810, and then $730, and so on.

This is exactly what happened during the Great Depression, when everyone was paying down debt and no one was borrowing and spending. From 1929 to 1933, the U.S. lost 46 percent of its GDP mostly because of this debt-repayment-induced deflationary spiral. It was also largely for this reason that the U.S. money supply shrank by nearly 30 percent during the four-year period.

The discussion above suggests that there are at least two types of recessions: those triggered by the usual business cycle and those triggered by private sector deleveraging or debt minimization. Since the economics profession never considered the latter type of recession, there is no name for it in the literature. In order to distinguish this type of recession from ordinary recessions, it is referred to here as a balance sheet recession. Like nationwide debt-financed bubbles, balance sheet recessions are rare and, left untreated, will ultimately develop into a depression.


Significance of Japanese experience

Japan faced a balance sheet recession following the bursting of its bubble in 1990 as commercial real estate prices fell 87 percent nationwide. The resulting loss of national wealth in shares and real estate alone was equivalent to three years of 1989 GDP. In comparison, the U.S. lost national wealth equivalent to one year of 1929 GDP during the Great Depression. Japan’s corporate sector responded by shifting from its traditional role as a large borrower of funds to a massive re-payer of debt, as shown in Exhibit 5. The net debt repayment of the corporate sector increased to more than 6 percent of GDP a year. And this was on top of household savings of over 4 percent of GDP a year, all with interest rates at zero. In other words, Japan could have lost 10 percent of GDP every year, just as the US did during the Great Depression.


Japan managed to avoid a depression, however, because the government borrowed and spent the aforementioned $100 every year, thereby keeping the economy’s expenditures at $1,000 ($900 in household spending plus $100 in government spending). In spite of a massive loss of wealth and private sector deleveraging reaching over 10 percent of GDP per year, Japan managed to keep its GDP above the bubble peak throughout the post-1990 era (Exhibit 6), and the unemployment rate never climbed above 5.5 percent.

This government action maintained incomes in the private sector and allowed businesses and households to pay down debt. By 2005 the private sector had completed its balance sheet repairs.

Although this fiscal action increased government debt by 460 trillion yen or 92 percent of GDP during the 1990–2005 period, the amount of GDP preserved by fiscal action compared with a depression scenario was far greater. For example, if we assume, rather optimistically, that without government action Japanese GDP would have returned to the pre-bubble level of 1985, the difference between this hypothetical GDP and actual GDP would be over 2,000 trillion yen for the 15-year period. In other words, Japan spent 460 trillion yen to buy 2,000 trillion yen of GDP, making it a tremendous bargain. And because the private sector was deleveraging, the government’s fiscal actions did not lead to crowding out, inflation, or skyrocketing interest rates.


Post-1990 Japan also managed to keep its money supply from falling in spite of private sector deleveraging because government borrowing took the place of private sector borrowing and prevented a contraction of banks’ assets. This is shown in Exhibit 7. The post-1933 U.S. money supply also stabilized and started growing again because the Roosevelt Administration began borrowing money aggressively for its New Deal programs, as shown in Exhibit 8.
  


Many authors have argued that it was monetary policy that led to the post-1933 U.S. recovery, but they all failed to look at the asset side of banks’ balance sheets. From 1933 to 1936, only lending to the government increased, while lending to the private sector did not increase at all. And lending to the government increased because the government had to finance the New Deal programs. Both of the examples above indicate that fiscal stimulus is essential in keeping both GDP and the money supply from contracting during a balance sheet recession.


The world in balance sheet recession

Today private sectors in the U.S., the U.K., Spain, and Ireland (but not Greece) are undergoing massive deleveraging in spite of record low interest rates. This means these countries are all in serious balance sheet recessions. The private sectors in Japan and Germany are not borrowing, either. With borrowers disappearing and banks reluctant to lend, it is no wonder that, after nearly three years of record low interest rates and massive liquidity injections, industrial economies are still doing so poorly.

Flow of funds data for the U.S. (Exhibit 9) show a massive shift away from borrowing to savings by the private sector since the housing bubble burst in 2007. The shift for the private sector as a whole represents over 9 percent of U.S. GDP at a time of zero interest rates. Moreover, this increase in private sector savings exceeds the increase in government borrowings (5.8 percent of GDP), which suggests that the government is not doing enough to offset private sector deleveraging.

Flow of funds data for the U.K. (Exhibit 10) tell the same story, with the growth in private savings (7.7 percent of GDP) exceeding the increase in government deficit (7.0 percent of GDP). Once again, this means the UK government is not doing enough to stabilize the economy by offsetting private sector deleveraging.

Yet policymakers in both countries, spooked by the events in Greece, have pushed strongly to cut budget deficits, with the U.K. pushing harder than the U.S. Although shunning fiscal profligacy is the right approach when the private sector is healthy and is maximizing profits, nothing is worse than fiscal consolidation when a sick private sector is minimizing debt. Removing government support in the midst of private sector deleveraging is equivalent to removing the aforementioned $100 from the economy’s income stream, and that will trigger a deflationary spiral as the economy shrinks from $1,000 to $900 to $810.

Unfortunately, the proponents of fiscal consolidation are only looking at the growth in the fiscal deficit while ignoring even bigger increases in private sector savings. Indeed these governments are repeating the Japanese mistake of premature fiscal consolidation in 1997 and 2001, which in both cases triggered a deflationary spiral and ultimately increased the deficit (Exhibit 11).


The mistake in 1997, for example, resulted in five quarters of negative growth and increased the deficit by 68 percent, from 22 trillion yen in 1996 to 38 trillion yen in 1999. It took Japan 10 years to climb out of the hole created by this policy error. Japan would have come out of its balance sheet recession much faster and at a significantly lower cost than the 460 trillion yen noted above had it not implemented austerity measures on those two occasions. The U.S. made the same mistake of premature fiscal consolidation in 1937, with equally devastating results.

Except for certain countries in the eurozone which will be discussed below, there is no reason why a government should face financing problems during a balance sheet recession. The amount of money it must borrow and spend to avert a deflationary spiral is exactly equal to the un-borrowed and un-invested savings in the private sector (the $100 mentioned above) that is sitting somewhere in the financial system.
With very few viable borrowers left in the private sector, fund managers who must invest in fixed income assets without foreign exchange risk have no choice but to lend to the government, which is the last borrower standing. Although deficit hawks pushing for fiscal consolidation often talk about “bond market vigilantes,” the fact that 10-year bond yields in the U.S. and U.K. today are only around 2 percent—unthinkably low given fiscal deficits of nearly ten percent of GDP—indicates that bond market participants are aware of the nature and dynamics of balance sheet recessions. Indeed bond yields in the U.S. and U.K. today are equivalent to Japanese bond yields in 1997.

Reason for eurozone debt crisis

While western economies experience balance sheet recessions and most government bond yields fall to historic lows, investors continue to demand high yields to hold the debt of eurozone countries like Spain and Ireland. The reason behind this phenomenon is a factor unique to the eurozone: fixed-income fund managers can buy government bonds issued by other eurozone countries without taking on any exchange rate risk. If they grow worried about their own government’s fiscal position, they can simply buy other governments’ debt.

Spain and Ireland, for instance, are both in serious balance sheet recessions, with private sector deleveraging reaching 17 percent of GDP in Spain (Exhibit 12) and a whopping 21 percent of GDP (Exhibit 13) in Ireland, all under record low interest rates. Indeed the entire eurozone is in a balance sheet recession (Exhibit 14). Even though this means there is huge pool of private sector savings available in these countries, Spanish and Irish pension fund managers who do not like their own countries’ debt can easily buy German government bonds. That leaves the governments of both Spain and Ireland unable to tap their own private savings surpluses to fight the balance sheet recessions.

If the governments of countries like Germany and the Netherlands actively borrow and spend the money flowing in from Spain and Ireland, that will sustain economic activity in the broader eurozone economy and have a positive impact on Spain and Ireland as well. Unfortunately, the governments of Germany and the Netherlands are focused entirely on deficit-reduction efforts in a bid to observe the 3% ceiling on budget deficits prescribed by the Maastricht Treaty.











Countries in balance sheet recessions such as Spain are desperately in need of fiscal stimulus but are unable to take advantage of the rapid increase in domestic savings and are therefore forced to engage in fiscal consolidation of their own. That causes the aforementioned $100 to be removed from the income steam, prompting a deflationary spiral. And since the countries receiving those savings are not borrowing and spending them, the broader eurozone economy is rapidly weakening. It is no wonder that the Spanish unemployment rate is over 21 percent and Irish GDP has fallen more than 10 percent from its peak.

Fund flows within the eurozone were following the opposite pattern until just a few years ago. Banks in Germany, which had fallen into a balance sheet recession after the telecom bubble collapsed in 2000, aggressively bought the debt of southern European nations, which were denominated in the same currency but offered higher yields than domestic debt. The resulting capital inflows from Germany poured further fuel onto the fire of housing bubbles in these countries.

There is thus a tendency within the eurozone for fund flows to go to extremes. When times are good, funds flow into booming economies in search of higher returns, thereby exacerbating the bubbles. When the bubbles finally burst, the funds shift suddenly to the countries least affected by the boom.

The problem with these shifts is that they are pro-cyclical, tending to amplify swings in the economy. Countries that are in the midst of a bubble and do not need or want additional funds experience massive inflows. Meanwhile, countries facing balance sheet recessions and in need of funds can only watch as money flows abroad, preventing their governments from implementing the fiscal stimulus needed to stabilize the economy.


Solution for Euro: allow only nationals to buy government bonds

One way to solve this eurozone-specific problem of capital shifts would be to prohibit member nations from selling government bonds to investors from other countries. Allowing only the citizens of a nation to hold that government’s debt would, for example, prevent the investment of Spanish savings in German government debt. Most of the Spanish savings that have been used to buy other countries’ government debt would therefore return to Spain. This would push Spanish government bond yields down to the levels observed in the U.S. and the U.K., thereby helping the Spanish government implement the fiscal stimulus required during a balance sheet recession.

The Maastricht Treaty with its rigid 3 percent GDP limit on budget deficits made no provision for balance sheet recessions. This is understandable given that the concept of balance sheet recessions did not exist when the Treaty was being negotiated in the 1990s. In contrast, the proposed new rule would allow individual governments to pursue autonomous fiscal policies within its constraint. In effect, governments could run larger deficits as long as they could persuade citizens to hold their debt. This would both instill discipline and provide flexibility to individual governments. By internalizing fiscal issues, the new rule would also free the European Central Bank from having to worry about fiscal issues in individual countries and allow it to focus its efforts on managing monetary policy.

In order to maximize efficiency gains in the single market, the new restriction should apply only to holdings of government bonds. German banks should still be allowed to buy Greek private sector debt, and Spanish banks should still be allowed to buy Dutch shares.

In retrospect, this rule should have been in place since the beginning of the euro. If that were the case, none of the problems the eurozone now faces would have materialized. Unfortunately, the euro was allowed to run for more than ten years without the rule, accumulating massive imbalances along the way. It may take many years to undo the damage.

In the meantime, it will be necessary to continue financing certain countries with bonds issued jointly by a body like the European Financial Stability Facility (EFSF). But compared with the present situation, where there is no end-game, the declaration of an end to member state sales of government bonds to other nationals five or ten years from now should help restore confidence in the euro. This is because none of the problems that have plagued the euro up to now would be repeated if the new rule were adopted.

Ending the eurozone’s crisis will require a two-pronged approach. First, international bodies like the EU and ECB need to declare that member countries experiencing balance sheet recessions must implement and maintain fiscal stimulus to support the economy until private sector balance sheets are repaired. Second, eurozone member nations must declare that in ten years they will prohibit the sale of government debt to anyone other than their own nationals.

The first prescription would provide the international organizations’ seal of approval for the fiscal stimulus needed to stabilize economies afflicted by balance sheet recessions, while the second would prohibit savings in countries like Spain from being invested in German government bonds. Without these two “game changers,” forcing eurozone nations in balance sheet recessions to engage in fiscal consolidation will simply make the problem worse.

Unfortunately, both ECB President Jean-Claude Trichet and BOE Chairman Mervyn King are still pushing for additional fiscal retrenchment. Among international organizations, only the IMF appears to have recognized the need for fiscal stimulus in countries facing balance sheet recessions.


Difficulty of maintaining fiscal stimulus in democracies

Federal Reserve Chairman Ben Bernanke understands the risk of balance sheet recessions and has been warning since early 2010 that now is not the time to engage in fiscal consolidation. Given that he was once a believer in the omnipotence of monetary policy, this represents a dramatic change of heart. Unfortunately, he and National Economic Council Chairman Gene Sperling are the only two officials openly pushing for fiscal stimulus: everyone else, including President Obama himself at times, seems to be in favor of fiscal consolidation. But with the U.S. private sector still deleveraging massively in spite of zero interest rates, nothing is potentially more dangerous for the U.S. economy than premature fiscal consolidation.

More broadly, recent developments in Washington, London, Madrid and other western capitals have proven that it is extremely difficult to maintain fiscal stimulus in a democracy during peacetime. This is a crucial problem during a balance sheet recession because fiscal stimulus must be maintained for the duration of the private sector deleveraging process in order to minimize both the length and the final fiscal cost of the recession. Unfortunately, in most democracies fiscal hawks are out in numbers demanding an end to fiscal stimulus as soon as the economy shows the first signs of life.

For example, many on both sides of the Atlantic have grown complacent after seeing certain economic and market indicators improve from their trough in the first half of 2009. The stock market, for example, was up nearly 60 percent at one point. Industrial production, which fell back to the level of 1998 in the U.S. and to the level of 1997 in the eurozone following the Lehman collapse, climbed back to the level of 2005 on both sides of the Atlantic, although it remains far below the peak levels of 2007.

This “recovery” has prompted a huge backlash from the Republican and Tea Party opposition in the U.S. seeking immediate fiscal consolidation. They argue that big government is bad government and that pork-barrel fiscal stimulus is costing future generations billions if not trillions. In the U.K., the Brown government, which implemented fiscal stimulus in 2009, was promptly voted out of office and replaced with the fiscal hawks of the Cameron government. In the eurozone, fiscal consolidation is now the only game in town. Even in Japan, the new DPJ government is pushing for a tax hike to pay for reconstruction work in the wake of the March 11th earthquake-tsunami-nuclear power plant disaster.

As a result of this backlash from fiscal hawks, the fiscal stimuli implemented by these countries in response to the Lehman–induced financial crisis are being allowed to expire. Private sector deleveraging, on the other hand, continues unabated at alarmingly high levels in all of these countries. Consequently, all of these economies are decelerating if not contracting altogether.

If the contraction appears serious and painful enough, the governments are likely to implement further fiscal stimulus, only to be forced back into fiscal consolidation once the stimulus breathes life back into the economy. This pattern of on-again, off-again fiscal stimulus is the reason why it took Japan 15 years to climb out of its own balance sheet recession. As shown in Exhibit 11, this policy zigzag, especially the austerity initiatives in 1997 and 2001, prolonged the recession by at least five years if not longer and added at least $1 trillion to the public debt unnecessarily. This policy zigzag also caused the disastrous collapse of the US economy in 1937.

Something else that slows down the implementation of fiscal stimulus in a democracy is the issue of how the money should be spent. As the previous example of 460 trillion yen in fiscal stimulus buying 2,000 trillion yen in Japanese GDP during the 1990–2005 period demonstrates, how the money is spent is largely irrelevant during a balance sheet recession: the important thing is that the money be spent.

In a democracy, however, where most people see only the trees and not the forest, even those few political leaders who understand the need for stimulus end up arguing endlessly about which projects the money should be spent on. In the meantime, the economy continues to shrink in the $1,000-to-$900-to-$810 deflationary spiral described above. Only during wartime, when it is obvious where the money should be spent, can democracies implement and sustain the kind of fiscal stimulus needed to overcome a balance sheet recession in the shortest possible time.

Even those who manage to prevent an economic meltdown by implementing necessary fiscal stimulus before the crisis are likely to be bashed instead of praised by the public. This is because the general public typically cannot envision what might have happened in the absence of fiscal stimulus. Seeing only a large deficit and no crisis, they assume the money must have been wasted on useless projects. That is exactly what happened to Liberal Democratic politicians in Japan, President Barack Obama in the U.S. and former Prime Minister Gordon Brown in the U.K. Although their actions saved their economies from devastating deflationary spirals, they were bashed because the public is unable to contemplate the counterfactual scenario. The man or woman who prevents a crisis never becomes a hero. For a hero to emerge we must first have a crisis, as Hollywood movies will attest.

It has also become popular in some circles to talk about medium-term fiscal consolidation while pushing for a short-term fiscal stimulus. Although this sounds responsible at one level, it is totally irresponsible at another. When the private sector is deleveraging in spite of zero interest rates, a condition that has never been anticipated in the economics or business literature, it is safe to assume that the private sector is very sick. Talking about medium-term consolidation in this environment is like asking a seriously injured person just admitted to an intensive care unit whether she can afford the expensive treatment needed. If asked this question enough times, the patient may become so depressed and discouraged that her condition will actually worsen, ultimately resulting in an even larger medical bill.

It has become commonplace to talk about the so-called policy duration effect of monetary policy. The July 2011 announcement by the Fed that it will not raise interest rates until well into 2013 was a prime example of maximizing this effect. For some reason, however, we hear nothing about the policy duration effect of fiscal policy. Talk of medium-term fiscal consolidation effectively minimizes the policy duration effect of whatever stimuli that are still in place, which in a sense is highly irresponsible. Since the patient must be cured somehow, the government should work to maximize the policy duration effect of both monetary and fiscal policies in order to minimize the final cost of treatment. It is never a good idea to depress both the brakes and the accelerator at the same time.

The above reality, together with the recent push for fiscal consolidation in Western capitals, suggests that it is difficult to maintain fiscal stimulus in a democracy during peacetime. Recovering from a balance sheet recession will therefore take a long time in a democracy.


“Exit problem” in balance sheet recessions

The long time required for the economy to pull out of a balance sheet recession means the private sector must spend many painful years paying down debt. That in turn brings about a debt “trauma” of sorts in which the private sector refuses to borrow money even after its balance sheet is fully repaired. This trauma may take years if not decades to overcome. But until the private sector is both willing and able to borrow again, the economy will be operating at less than full potential and may require continued fiscal support from the government to stay afloat. Overcoming this trauma may be called the “exit problem.”

In Japan, where the private sector has grown extremely averse to borrowing after its bitter experience of paying down debt from 1990 to 2005, businesses are not borrowing money in spite of willing lenders and the lowest interest rates in human history. As a result, the 10-year government bond is yielding only around 1 percent even though government debt amounts to nearly 200 percent of GDP. 

thirty years, until 1959 (Exhibit 15). The fact that it took the U.S. three decades to bring interest rates back up to 4 percent even with massive fiscal stimuli in the form of the New Deal and World War II suggests the severity of the trauma. Indeed many of those Americans forced to pay down debt during the Depression never borrowed again.

The experiences of post-1929 US and post-1990 Japan suggest that interest rates will remain low for a very long time even after private sector balance sheets are repaired. The governments of countries facing exit problems should therefore introduce incentives for businesses to borrow. Such incentives, which may include investment tax credits and accelerated depreciation allowances, should be exceptionally generous in order to attract private sector attention. The sooner the trauma is overcome, the sooner the government can embark on fiscal consolidation. The generosity will more than pay for itself once the private sector trauma is overcome.


Ending panic was the easy part; rebuilding balance sheets is the hard part

A distinction should also be drawn between balance sheet recessions and financial crises, since both are present in the post-Lehman debacle. The former is a borrower’s phenomenon, while the latter is a lender’s phenomenon. This distinction is important because the economic “recovery” starting in 2009 has been largely limited to a recovery from the policy mistake of allowing Lehman Brothers to fail. The collapse of Lehman sparked a global financial crisis that weakened the economy far more severely and rapidly than what would have been suggested by balance sheet problems alone.

Unlike balance sheet recessions, in which monetary policy is largely impotent, financial crises can and must be addressed by the monetary authorities. Available tools include liquidity infusions, capital injections, explicit and implicit guarantees, lower interest rates and asset purchases. According to IMF figures, the Federal Reserve, together with governments and central banks around the world, injected some $8.9 trillion in liquidity and guarantees for this purpose in the wake of the Lehman shock.

The Lehman panic was caused by the government’s decision not to safeguard the liabilities of a major financial institution when so many institutions had similar problems. Consequently, the panic dissipated when the authorities moved to safeguard those liabilities. That was the “recovery” observed in some quarters since the spring of 2009.

Although the panic has subsided, all the balance sheet problems that existed before the Lehman failure are still in place. If anything, the continuous fall in house prices since then has exacerbated these problems. Balance sheet problems are likely to slow down the recovery or derail it altogether unless the government moves to offset the deflationary pressure coming from private sector deleveraging. In other words, the recovery so far was the easy part ((B) in Exhibit 16). The hard work of repairing millions of impaired private sector balance sheets is just beginning ((A) in Exhibit 16).

Conclusion

It is laudable for policy makers to shun fiscal profligacy and aim for self-reliance on the part of the private sector. But every several decades, the private sector loses its self-control in a bubble and sustains heavy financial injuries when the bubble bursts. That forces the private sector to pay down debt in spite of zero interest rates, triggering a deflationary spiral. At such times and at such times only, the government must borrow and spend the private sector’s excess savings, not only because monetary policy is impotent at such times but also because the government cannot tell the private sector not to repair its balance sheet.

Although anyone can push for fiscal consolidation in the form of higher taxes and lower spending, whether such efforts actually succeed in reducing the budget deficit is another matter entirely. When the private sector is both willing and able to borrow money, fiscal consolidation efforts by the government will lead to a smaller deficit and higher growth as resources are released to the more efficient private sector. But when the financial health of the private sector is so impaired that it is forced to deleverage even with interest rates at zero, a premature withdrawal of fiscal stimulus will both increase the deficit and weaken the economy. Key differences between the textbook world and the world of balance sheet recessions are summarized in Exhibit 17.

With massive private sector deleveraging continuing in the U.S. and in many other countries in spite of historically low interest rates, this is no time to embark on fiscal consolidation. Such measures must wait until it is certain the private sector has finished deleveraging and is ready to borrow and spend the savings that would be left un-borrowed by the government under an austerity program.
There will be plenty of time to pay down the accumulated public debt because the next balance sheet recession of this magnitude is likely to be generations away, given that those who learned a bitter lesson in the present episode will not make the same mistake again. The next bubble and balance sheet recession of this magnitude will happen only after we are no longer here to remember them.





Aaron’s, Inc (NYSE: AAN)


December 2, 2019



With the S&P 500 and DJIA at an all-time high, most investors find it hard to find bargain securities at depressed prices. Stocks are rising despite a lack of corresponding real performance in earnings or production; coupled with the trade war and a changing yield curve, investors anticipate a dip looming, but no one truly knows when.

Lease to own, virtual leasing, and retail companies have benefited from this boom. However, the lease-to-own industry is changing to an online business model, and as consumers get more financially savvy, they may opt for credit cards instead. Important industry metrics for lease-to-own goods are comparable store sales, invoices grown, and invoices per active door count.

Aaron’s has taken advantage of this boom by buying up Progressive’s product leasing division for approximately $700million in 2014. Aaron’s higher operating margins are due to Progressive’s cooperation with large enterprise accounts vs purchasing store owned merchandise. Progressive Leasing acts as a lease to ownership facilitator— Progressive partners with different retailers to provide customers with poorer FICO (600-700) or credit ratings with lease-to-own agreements for products outside of Aaron's coverage. 

In 2019, Progressive partnered with BestBuy in February and Wayfair in October. Despite these positive partnerships, the nature of the lease-to-own retail industry is that it will experience cyclical downturns especially with Aaron’s heavy product range in appliances and furniture. Before the Progressive acquisition, Aaron’s legacy business’ operating margins were still in single digits.

John Robinson, Aaron’s current CEO, previously ran an auto-title lender called TitleMax, growing the company from approximately 100 stores to more than 750 stores. Robinson and has team have now solidified Aaron’s position as the US lease-to-own market leader with a capitalization of 4 billion with 1689 stores and operating margins of 13.8% as of December 2018. Competitor Rent-A-Center has a capitalization of 1.4 billion, has 2561 stores, but almost half the operating margins at 6.2%. Both companies are benefiting with E-commerce, with Rent-A-Center generating 80% of its new customers online, while Aaron’s saw a 68% increase in e-commerce lease-to-own revenues in 2019.

Progressive now carries the weight for Aaron’s future prospects, since its legacy leasing and brick and mortar business is deteriorating. Invoice numbers are an excellent predictor of revenue performance, while other figures come with a trade-off. Since acquisition, Progressive has grown customer leasing invoice volume from 471 million in 2014 to 1.49 billion in 2019, with 2.46 billion of lease agreements in effect.

Progressive’s leasing business uses proprietary algorithms to determine whether customers meet leasing qualifications with the ability to turn on and off different pools of opportunity and approval rates. Progressive’s system is really agile, while on the other hand, there are many problems with Aaron's legacy retail business–their old technology makes them non-competitive. Progressive has been helping Aaron’s make a transition, by having 40-50 trial stores with new technology and trained staff, but whether this strategy proves successful and well executed poses a risk to shareholders.

Most of Progressive’s transactions are completed online or through a point of sale integration with retail partners. Contractual payments are usually based on a customer's pay frequency and are typically processed through automated clearing house payments. If the payment is unsuccessful, collections are managed in-house through a call center, customer service hubs, and a proprietary lease management system. The call center contacts customers within a few days after the due date to encourage them to pay on time. If the customer chooses to return the merchandise, arrangements are made to receive the merchandise through retail partners, or Aaron's operated stores.

Despite Progressive’s complex algorithms to screen candidates for credit-worthiness, their rapid and aggressive expansion always makes me consider whether there are conservative factors embedded in screening candidates.

Progressive calculates, at the end of each period, the allowance for loan losses based on actual delinquency balances. Delinquent loans receivable are those that are 30 days or more past due based on their contractual billing dates. Progressive then evaluates the historical average loss for the prior eight quarters on loans receivable by aging category.

Aaron’s places loans receivable on nonaccrual status when they are greater than 90 days past due or upon notification of client bankruptcy, death or fraud. For loans in nonaccrual status, Aaron’s discontinues accruing interest and fees. The allowance for loan losses is maintained at an adequate level to cover probable losses of principal, interest and fees in the loans receivable portfolio.

Loans receivable are removed from nonaccrual status when payments resume, the loan becomes 90 days or less past due and collection of outstanding amounts is deemed probable. Payments received on nonaccrual loans are allocated according to the same payment ranking system applied to loans accruing interest. Loans receivable 120 days past due are charged off at the end of the month following the billing cycle.

Progressive Leasing had 953,000 customers at September 30, 2019, a 17.9% increase from September 30, 2018. Despite sales are growing about 30% year on year, Aaron’s quickly depreciating merchandise (Progressive and Aarons has roughly half of its leasing in furniture, a quarter in appliances, and a quarter in electronics) and poor same store sales growth (-7% in 2017 and -1.5% in 2018) in an attempt to restructure its legacy business makes investing in Aaron’s fraught with risk. Aaron's lease ownership requires significant levels of merchandise inventory available for lease in order to ensure timely delivery of products for store-based and e-commerce operations. Therefore, Aaron's most significant working capital asset is merchandise inventory on lease.

Aaron’s has 1312 stores which are wholly owned, and 377 franchised stores. Aaron’s also has its own furniture brand called Woodhaven. About a third of Aaron’s stores are franchisees, and that number is shrinking. In 2017, Aaron’s largest franchisee, SEI, was acquired in an all cash transaction for 140 million which included coverage of 11 states and 90,000 customers mainly in the North East.

Company-operated Aaron’s stores had 963,000 customers in September 30, 2019, a 2.6% decrease from September 30, 2018. This transition turns Aaron's Business segment into a more capital-intensive business model due to real estate and additional costs associated instead of collecting a franchise fee.

When Aaron’s enters into franchise agreements, they govern the opening and operations of franchised stores. Under the standard agreement, Aaron’s receives a franchise fee for a term of ten years, with one ten-year renewal option from $15,000 to $50,000 per store depending upon market size. Franchisees are also obligated to remit to royalty payments of 6% of the weekly cash revenue collections from their stores.

Same-store revenues for franchised stores increased 1.7% and same-store customer counts declined 3.7% for the third quarter of 2019 compared with the same 3rd quarter in 2018. Franchised stores had 241,000 customers at the end of the third quarter of 2019.

Aaron’s tried to minimize expenses after acquisition of SEI by shutting down 155 stores in 2019. To a certain extent, gaining ownership of retail franchise stores is a liability rather than an asset. The good news is, in Aaron’s recent conference call, directors claim— “We do not have any material franchise acquisitions planned at this time. However, we would certainly evaluate the right opportunity were it to present itself.”

Another risk with from significant increase in deliveries results in insufficient labor to handle the workload in stores. Aaron’s provides durable household goods such as furniture on monthly, semi-monthly, and weekly installments. Aaron’s also guarantees same or next day delivery for customers ten miles from the store. This labor shortage hampers collections performance, which had an unfavorable impact on lease revenues and write-offs.

Aaron’s also experienced a decrease in active door count primarily due to a reduction in locations in mattress and mobile phone segments. Q3 2019 active door count was approximately 19,900, down 1.6% from the third quarter of 2018. In terms of active doors, a metric for Progressive’s virtual lease to own transactions there were 24,198 in 2018 and 21,840 in 2016.

Management and Aaron’s CEO John Robinson believes that invoices per active door count has become less predictive as a leading indicator of future revenue growth, particularly as overall mix shifts towards larger footprint locations and e-commerce transactions (virtual leasing) or larger footprint type doors. A new influx of invoices can come in without necessarily moving the door metric as seen in the past.

Should a recession scenario occur, Aaron’s might gain more customers, due to customers with poorer credit ratings seeking to purchase goods. But there is also a chance the legacy business might fail weather the storm. Factors to consider are with Aaron’s being more lenient in accepting leasing for goods—will there be increasing defaults? Will the business model become obsolete as customers get more responsible?

Aaron’s customers are non-sophisticated customers with limited access to traditional credit based bank financing, installment credit cards. This is bad since the majority of Americans are in the upper tiers of the FICO scoring distribution—nearly 57% of Americans have a FICO score of 700 or higher. This has historically been the case, but in the last eight or ten years of steady economic growth since the 2008 financial crisis most American consumer’s credit profiles have improved significantly. As Americans become more responsible and credit worthy, they would gradually make the switch to credit cards and traditional bank financing.

Another factor to consider is – with electronics and mobile phones depreciating at a quick rate and since only a certain amount of consumer durables are considered a necessity, would people stop buying and leasing certain goods in a recession? Progressive’s average lease life is 7 months and has superior analytics and faster collection compared to Aaron’s legacy business. Despite Aaron’s being able to buy at better rates due to relationships with large electronics manufacturers like Samsung, too many goods in electronics and appliances become obsolete within a year.

From 2017-2019, the write-offs for damaged, lost or unsaleable merchandise ranged from 5-8% of gross revenues. There was a slight increase in writes-offs due to a reduction in collections from the implementation and adoption of new sales programs, and store closures. Bad debt ranged from 10-13%. Performance differed due to restructuring of legacy stores and an increasing mix of virtual leasing added to the revenue stream.

For Aaron’s you can expect annual capital expenditures to continue to be in the 100-130 million dollar range. With 60-70 million for maintenance capital expenditures and the rest for expansion. Expansion or growth capital expenditures is focused in 3 areas—

1.      Due to the change in lease accounting, Aaron’s reevaluated their vehicle acquisition strategy and plans to purchase trucks in the Aaron's Business instead of leasing them going forward. The incremental capital expenditures for trucks should be approximately $15 million for 2019.

2.      Another $15 million relates to both hardware and software to complete the rollout of rapid customer onboarding, centralized processing, and IT based customer support for Aaron's Business.

3.      Finally, the new store concept and the restructuring of stores is being implemented. The improvements include an increase in deliveries in excess of 30%. Aaron’s has increased their sample set by 40 to 50 locations during 2019. We expect to spend approximately $30 million for these real estate-related improvements.

Aaron’s management deems it prudent to confirm results of these 40-50 locations before deciding on a possible broader rollout.

During Q2 2019 Aaron’s returned approximately $27 million to shareholders through buybacks repurchased approximately 243,000 shares, returning approximately $17 million to shareholders. In Q3 2019, with 150 million in cash, Aaron’s repurchased 399,424 shares for 25 million at an average price of 62 dollars per share. Despite buybacks and dividends, one negative sign suggesting management may not be aligned and incentivized in the same interests as shareholders is that the board of directors and executive team own less than 2% of Aaron’s. Aaron’s has had one 3-for-2 stock split in 2011 and hasn’t had any splits since.

Aaron's, Inc. directors raise quarterly cash dividends by 14.3% from $0.04 per share from $0.035, and declared the first such dividend payable January 6, 2020 to shareholders of record as of the close of business on December 19, 2019.
Aaron’s dividend has been raised for 17 consecutive intervals and has not been omitted.

Credit and appliance rentals a 20-25 billion market in the US. With approximately 40% of the US population carrying a FICO score under 700, there is still a large enough addressable market that the business can continue growing. Of the whole market, if Aaron’s targets the 40% within its FICO range, this mean 8-12 billion of Aaron’s customers are untapped. Being conservative, if the market doesn’t grow, due to an inability to partner with enterprises or consumers becoming wiser and not leasing goods to own them later; at most, there is room for Aaron’s market capitalization to double or maybe, very remotely, triple. I don’t foresee Aaron’s expanding internationally soon.  

One positive sign is that Aaron’s return on capital has been continuously increasing, and is now at 14%. Days-payable has decreased from 68 days in 2014 to 15 days in 2019, which warrants further investigation. Tangible book value has more than doubled since 2014, from 360 million to 933 million in 2019.

Debt to equity has decreased from 50% in 2014 to 38% in 2019. Aaron’s amended its revolving credit facility and term loan agreement to increase its term loan by $137.5 million, to $225 million. Aaron’s also amended its franchise loan facility to reduce the total commitment amount from $85 million to $55 million and extend the maturity to October 22, 2019.

Will Aaron's be able to turn its legacy business around? Will the 40-50 trial stores work out and be rolled out nation-wide? Or will this legacy business cancel out benefits accrued from Progressive? Despite partnerships with Bestbuy and Wayfair, will bigger players like Walmart and Amazon disrupt this field?

At a present price of about 4.5 billion inclusive of debt, and a predicted consistent earning power of 300 million a year, 15 times earnings seems to be a bit too expensive despite Aaron’s growth potential should it fix its traditional business and expand further. While Aaron’s is by no means very cheap at 8.4x enterprise value to operating earnings, it is cheaper than its peers which are near 15-16x earnings.

I would wait until there’s a dip of 50-70% so enterprise value is closer to 2 billion or not buy at all. Even if I were to own this business, I don’t see it as a great business model over the next decade.